<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0068" id="link2HCH0068"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER XI——OF CRUELTY </h2>
<p>I fancy virtue to be something else, and something more noble, than good
nature, and the mere propension to goodness, that we are born into the
world withal. Well-disposed and well-descended souls pursue, indeed, the
same methods, and represent in their actions the same face that virtue
itself does: but the word virtue imports, I know not what, more great and
active than merely for a man to suffer himself, by a happy disposition, to
be gently and quietly drawn to the rule of reason. He who, by a natural
sweetness and facility, should despise injuries received, would doubtless
do a very fine and laudable thing; but he who, provoked and nettled to the
quick by an offence, should fortify himself with the arms of reason
against the furious appetite of revenge, and after a great conflict,
master his own passion, would certainly do a great deal more. The first
would do well; the latter virtuously: one action might be called goodness,
and the other virtue; for methinks, the very name of virtue presupposes
difficulty and contention, and cannot be exercised without an opponent.
'Tis for this reason, perhaps, that we call God good, mighty, liberal and
just; but we do not call Him virtuous, being that all His operations are
natural and without endeavour.—[Rousseau, in his Emile, book v.,
adopts this passage almost in the same words.]— It has been the
opinion of many philosophers, not only Stoics, but Epicureans—and
this addition—</p>
<p>["Montaigne stops here to make his excuse for thus naming the<br/>
Epicureans with the Stoics, in conformity to the general opinion<br/>
that the Epicureans were not so rigid in their morals as the Stoics,<br/>
which is not true in the main, as he demonstrates at one view. This<br/>
involved Montaigne in a tedious parenthesis, during which it is<br/>
proper that the reader be attentive, that he may not entirely lose<br/>
the thread of the argument. In some later editions of this author,<br/>
it has been attempted to remedy this inconvenience, but without<br/>
observing that Montaigne's argument is rendered more feeble and<br/>
obscure by such vain repetitions: it is a licence that ought not to<br/>
be taken, because he who publishes the work of another, ought to<br/>
give it as the other composed ft. But, in Mr Cotton's translation,<br/>
he was so puzzled with this enormous parenthesis that he has quite<br/>
left it out"—Coste.]<br/></p>
<p>I borrow from the vulgar opinion, which is false, notwithstanding the
witty conceit of Arcesilaus in answer to one, who, being reproached that
many scholars went from his school to the Epicurean, but never any from
thence to his school, said in answer, "I believe it indeed; numbers of
capons being made out of cocks, but never any cocks out of capons."
—[Diogenes Laertius, Life of Archesilaus, lib. iv., 43.]—For,
in truth, the Epicurean sect is not at all inferior to the Stoic in
steadiness, and the rigour of opinions and precepts. And a certain Stoic,
showing more honesty than those disputants, who, in order to quarrel with
Epicurus, and to throw the game into their hands, make him say what he
never thought, putting a wrong construction upon his words, clothing his
sentences, by the strict rules of grammar, with another meaning, and a
different opinion from that which they knew he entertained in his mind and
in his morals, the Stoic, I say, declared that he abandoned the Epicurean
sect, upon this among other considerations, that he thought their road too
lofty and inaccessible;</p>
<p>["And those are called lovers of pleasure, being in effect<br/>
lovers of honour and justice, who cultivate and observe all<br/>
the virtues."—Cicero, Ep. Fam., xv. i, 19.]<br/></p>
<p>These philosophers say that it is not enough to have the soul seated in a
good place, of a good temper, and well disposed to virtue; it is not
enough to have our resolutions and our reasoning fixed above all the power
of fortune, but that we are, moreover, to seek occasions wherein to put
them to the proof: they would seek pain, necessity, and contempt to
contend with them and to keep the soul in breath:</p>
<p>"Multum sibi adjicit virtus lacessita."<br/>
<br/>
["Virtue is much strengthened by combats."<br/>
or: "Virtue attacked adds to its own force."<br/>
—Seneca, Ep., 13.]<br/></p>
<p>'Tis one of the reasons why Epaminondas, who was yet of a third sect,
—[The Pythagorean.]—refused the riches fortune presented to
him by very lawful means; because, said he, I am to contend with poverty,
in which extreme he maintained himself to the last. Socrates put himself,
methinks, upon a ruder trial, keeping for his exercise a confounded
scolding wife, which was fighting at sharps. Metellus having, of all the
Roman senators, alone attempted, by the power of virtue, to withstand the
violence of Saturninus, tribune of the people at Rome, who would, by all
means, cause an unjust law to pass in favour of the commons, and, by so
doing, having incurred the capital penalties that Saturninus had
established against the dissentient, entertained those who, in this
extremity, led him to execution with words to this effect: That it was a
thing too easy and too base to do ill; and that to do well where there was
no danger was a common thing; but that to do well where there was danger
was the proper office of a man of virtue. These words of Metellus very
clearly represent to us what I would make out, viz., that virtue refuses
facility for a companion; and that the easy, smooth, and descending way by
which the regular steps of a sweet disposition of nature are conducted is
not that of a true virtue; she requires a rough and stormy passage; she
will have either exotic difficulties to wrestle with, like that of
Metellus, by means whereof fortune delights to interrupt the speed of her
career, or internal difficulties, that the inordinate appetites and
imperfections of our condition introduce to disturb her.</p>
<p>I am come thus far at my ease; but here it comes into my head that the
soul of Socrates, the most perfect that ever came to my knowledge, should
by this rule be of very little recommendation; for I cannot conceive in
that person any the least motion of a vicious inclination: I cannot
imagine there could be any difficulty or constraint in the course of his
virtue: I know his reason to be so powerful and sovereign over him that
she would never have suffered a vicious appetite so much as to spring in
him. To a virtue so elevated as his, I have nothing to oppose. Methinks I
see him march, with a victorious and triumphant pace, in pomp and at his
ease, without opposition or disturbance. If virtue cannot shine bright,
but by the conflict of contrary appetites, shall we then say that she
cannot subsist without the assistance of vice, and that it is from her
that she derives her reputation and honour? What then, also, would become
of that brave and generous Epicurean pleasure, which makes account that it
nourishes virtue tenderly in her lap, and there makes it play and wanton,
giving it for toys to play withal, shame, fevers, poverty, death, and
torments? If I presuppose that a perfect virtue manifests itself in
contending, in patient enduring of pain, and undergoing the uttermost
extremity of the gout; without being moved in her seat; if I give her
troubles and difficulty for her necessary objects: what will become of a
virtue elevated to such a degree, as not only to despise pain, but,
moreover, to rejoice in it, and to be tickled with the throes of a sharp
colic, such as the Epicureans have established, and of which many of them,
by their actions, have given most manifest proofs? As have several others,
who I find to have surpassed in effects even the very rules of their
discipline. Witness the younger Cato: When I see him die, and tearing out
his own bowels, I am not satisfied simply to believe that he had then his
soul totally exempt from all trouble and horror: I cannot think that he
only maintained himself in the steadiness that the Stoical rules
prescribed him; temperate, without emotion, and imperturbed. There was,
methinks, something in the virtue of this man too sprightly and fresh to
stop there; I believe that, without doubt, he felt a pleasure and delight
in so noble an action, and was more pleased in it than in any other of his
life:</p>
<p>"Sic abiit a vita, ut causam moriendi nactum se esse gauderet."<br/>
<br/>
["He quitted life rejoicing that a reason for dying had arisen."<br/>
—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., i. 30.]<br/></p>
<p>I believe it so thoroughly that I question whether he would have been
content to have been deprived of the occasion of so brave an exploit; and
if the goodness that made him embrace the public concern more than his
own, withheld me not, I should easily fall into an opinion that he thought
himself obliged to fortune for having put his virtue upon so brave a
trial, and for having favoured that theif—[Caesar]—in treading
underfoot the ancient liberty of his country. Methinks I read in this
action I know not what exaltation in his soul, and an extraordinary and
manly emotion of pleasure, when he looked upon the generosity and height
of his enterprise:</p>
<p>"Deliberate morte ferocior,"<br/>
<br/>
["The more courageous from the deliberation to die."<br/>
—Horace, Od., i. 37, 29.]<br/></p>
<p>not stimulated with any hope of glory, as the popular and effeminate
judgments of some have concluded (for that consideration was too mean and
low to possess so generous, so haughty, and so determined a heart as his),
but for the very beauty of the thing in itself, which he who had the
handling of the springs discerned more clearly and in its perfection than
we are able to do. Philosophy has obliged me in determining that so brave
an action had been indecently placed in any other life than that of Cato;
and that it only appertained to his to end so; notwithstanding, and
according to reason, he commanded his son and the senators who accompanied
him to take another course in their affairs:</p>
<p>"Catoni, quum incredibilem natura tribuisset gravitatem,<br/>
eamque ipse perpetue constantia roboravisset, semperque<br/>
in proposito consilio permansisset, moriendum potius,<br/>
quam tyranni vultus aspiciendus, erat."<br/>
<br/>
["Cato, whom nature had given incredible dignity, which he had<br/>
fortified by perpetual constancy, ever remaining of his<br/>
predetermined opinion, preferred to die rather than to look<br/>
on the countenance of a tyrant."—Cicero, De Ofc., i. 31.]<br/></p>
<p>Every death ought to hold proportion with the life before it; we do not
become others for dying. I always interpret the death by the life
preceding; and if any one tell me of a death strong and constant in
appearance, annexed to a feeble life, I conclude it produced by some
feeble cause, and suitable to the life before. The easiness then of his
death and the facility of dying he had acquired by the vigour of his soul;
shall we say that it ought to abate anything of the lustre of his virtue?
And who, that has his brain never so little tinctured with the true
philosophy, can be content to imagine Socrates only free from fear and
passion in the accident of his prison, fetters, and condemnation? and that
will not discover in him not only firmness and constancy (which was his
ordinary condition), but, moreover, I know not what new satisfaction, and
a frolic cheerfulness in his last words and actions? In the start he gave
with the pleasure of scratching his leg when his irons were taken off,
does he not discover an equal serenity and joy in his soul for being freed
from past inconveniences, and at the same time to enter into the knowledge
of the things to come? Cato shall pardon me, if he please; his death
indeed is more tragical and more lingering; but yet this is, I know not
how, methinks, finer. Aristippus, to one that was lamenting this death:
"The gods grant me such an one," said he. A man discerns in the soul of
these two great men and their imitators (for I very much doubt whether
there were ever their equals) so perfect a habitude to virtue, that it was
turned to a complexion. It is no longer a laborious virtue, nor the
precepts of reason, to maintain which the soul is so racked, but the very
essence of their soul, its natural and ordinary habit; they have rendered
it such by a long practice of philosophical precepts having lit upon a
rich and fine nature; the vicious passions that spring in us can find no
entrance into them; the force and vigour of their soul stifle and
extinguish irregular desires, so soon as they begin to move.</p>
<p>Now, that it is not more noble, by a high and divine resolution, to hinder
the birth of temptations, and to be so formed to virtue, that the very
seeds of vice are rooted out, than to hinder by main force their progress;
and, having suffered ourselves to be surprised with the first motions of
the passions, to arm ourselves and to stand firm to oppose their progress,
and overcome them; and that this second effect is not also much more
generous than to be simply endowed with a facile and affable nature, of
itself disaffected to debauchery and vice, I do not think can be doubted;
for this third and last sort of virtue seems to render a man innocent, but
not virtuous; free from doing ill, but not apt enough to do well:
considering also, that this condition is so near neighbour to imperfection
and cowardice, that I know not very well how to separate the confines and
distinguish them: the very names of goodness and innocence are, for this
reason, in some sort grown into contempt. I very well know that several
virtues, as chastity, sobriety, and temperance, may come to a man through
personal defects. Constancy in danger, if it must be so called, the
contempt of death, and patience in misfortunes, may ofttimes be found in
men for want of well judging of such accidents, and not apprehending them
for such as they are. Want of apprehension and stupidity sometimes
counterfeit virtuous effects as I have often seen it happen, that men have
been commended for what really merited blame. An Italian lord once said
this, in my presence, to the disadvantage of his own nation: that the
subtlety of the Italians, and the vivacity of their conceptions were so
great, and they foresaw the dangers and accidents that might befall them
so far off, that it was not to be thought strange, if they were often, in
war, observed to provide for their safety, even before they had discovered
the peril; that we French and the Spaniards, who were not so cunning, went
on further, and that we must be made to see and feel the danger before we
would take the alarm; but that even then we could not stick to it. But the
Germans and Swiss, more gross and heavy, had not the sense to look about
them, even when the blows were falling about their ears. Peradventure, he
only talked so for mirth's sake; and yet it is most certain that in war
raw soldiers rush into dangers with more precipitancy than after they have
been cudgelled*—(The original has eschauldex—scalded)</p>
<p>"Haud ignarus . . . . quantum nova gloria in armis,<br/>
Et praedulce decus, primo certamine possit."<br/>
<br/>
["Not ignorant how much power the fresh glory of arms and sweetest<br/>
honour possess in the first contest."—AEneid, xi. 154]<br/></p>
<p>For this reason it is that, when we judge of a particular action, we are
to consider the circumstances, and the whole man by whom it is performed,
before we give it a name.</p>
<p>To instance in myself: I have sometimes known my friends call that
prudence in me, which was merely fortune; and repute that courage and
patience, which was judgment and opinion; and attribute to me one title
for another, sometimes to my advantage and sometimes otherwise. As to the
rest, I am so far from being arrived at the first and most perfect degree
of excellence, where virtue is turned into habit, that even of the second
I have made no great proofs. I have not been very solicitous to curb the
desires by which I have been importuned. My virtue is a virtue, or rather
an innocence, casual and accidental. If I had been born of a more
irregular complexion, I am afraid I should have made scurvy work; for I
never observed any great stability in my soul to resist passions, if they
were never so little vehement: I know not how to nourish quarrels and
debates in my own bosom, and, consequently, owe myself no great thanks
that I am free from several vices:</p>
<p>"Si vitiis mediocribus et mea paucis<br/>
Mendosa est natura, alioqui recta, velut si<br/>
Egregio inspersos reprehendas corpore naevos:"<br/>
<br/>
["If my nature be disfigured only with slight and few vices, and is<br/>
otherwise just, it is as if you should blame moles on a fair body."<br/>
—Horatius, Sat., i. 6, 65.]<br/></p>
<p>I owe it rather to my fortune than my reason. She has caused me to be
descended of a race famous for integrity and of a very good father; I know
not whether or no he has infused into me part of his humours, or whether
domestic examples and the good education of my infancy have insensibly
assisted in the work, or, if I was otherwise born so:</p>
<p>"Seu Libra, seu me Scorpius adspicit<br/>
Formidolosus, pars violentior<br/>
Natalis hors, seu tyrannus<br/>
Hesperive Capricornus undae:"<br/>
<br/>
["Whether the Balance or dread Scorpio, more potent over my natal<br/>
hour, aspects me, or Capricorn, supreme over the Hesperian sea."<br/>
—Horace, Od., ii. 117.]<br/></p>
<p>but so it is, that I have naturally a horror for most vices. The answer of
Antisthenes to him who asked him, which was the best apprenticeship "to
unlearn evil," seems to point at this. I have them in horror, I say, with
a detestation so natural, and so much my own, that the same instinct and
impression I brought of them with me from my nurse, I yet retain, and no
temptation whatever has had the power to make me alter it. Not so much as
my own discourses, which in some things lashing out of the common road
might seem easily to license me to actions that my natural inclination
makes me hate. I will say a prodigious thing, but I will say it, however:
I find myself in many things more under reputation by my manners than by
my opinion, and my concupiscence less debauched than my reason. Aristippus
instituted opinions so bold in favour of pleasure and riches as set all
the philosophers against him: but as to his manners, Dionysius the tyrant,
having presented three beautiful women before him, to take his choice; he
made answer, that he would choose them all, and that Paris got himself
into trouble for having preferred one before the other two: but, having
taken them home to his house, he sent them back untouched. His servant
finding himself overladen upon the way, with the money he carried after
him, he ordered him to pour out and throw away that which troubled him.
And Epicurus, whose doctrines were so irreligious and effeminate, was in
his life very laborious and devout; he wrote to a friend of his that he
lived only upon biscuit and water, entreating him to send him a little
cheese, to lie by him against he had a mind to make a feast. Must it be
true, that to be a perfect good man, we must be so by an occult, natural,
and universal propriety, without law, reason, or example? The debauches
wherein I have been engaged, have not been, I thank God, of the worst
sort, and I have condemned them in myself, for my judgment was never
infected by them; on the contrary, I accuse them more severely in myself
than in any other; but that is all, for, as to the rest. I oppose too
little resistance and suffer myself to incline too much to the other side
of the balance, excepting that I moderate them, and prevent them from
mixing with other vices, which for the most part will cling together, if a
man have not a care. I have contracted and curtailed mine, to make them as
single and as simple as I can:</p>
<p>"Nec ultra<br/>
Errorem foveo."<br/>
<br/>
["Nor do I cherish error further."<br/>
or: "Nor carry wrong further."<br/>
—Juvenal, viii. 164.]<br/></p>
<p>For as to the opinion of the Stoics, who say, "That the wise man when he
works, works by all the virtues together, though one be most apparent,
according to the nature of the action"; and herein the similitude of a
human body might serve them somewhat, for the action of anger cannot work,
unless all the humours assist it, though choler predominate; —if
they will thence draw a like consequence, that when the wicked man does
wickedly, he does it by all the vices together, I do not believe it to be
so, or else I understand them not, for I by effect find the contrary.
These are sharp, unsubstantial subleties, with which philosophy sometimes
amuses itself. I follow some vices, but I fly others as much as a saint
would do. The Peripatetics also disown this indissoluble connection; and
Aristotle is of opinion that a prudent and just man may be intemperate and
inconsistent. Socrates confessed to some who had discovered a certain
inclination to vice in his physiognomy, that it was, in truth, his natural
propension, but that he had by discipline corrected it. And such as were
familiar with the philosopher Stilpo said, that being born with addiction
to wine and women, he had by study rendered himself very abstinent both
from the one and the other.</p>
<p>What I have in me of good, I have, quite contrary, by the chance of my
birth; and hold it not either by law, precept, or any other instruction;
the innocence that is in me is a simple one; little vigour and no art.
Amongst other vices, I mortally hate cruelty, both by nature and judgment,
as the very extreme of all vices: nay, with so much tenderness that I
cannot see a chicken's neck pulled off without trouble, and cannot without
impatience endure the cry of a hare in my dog's teeth, though the chase be
a violent pleasure. Such as have sensuality to encounter, freely make use
of this argument, to shew that it is altogether "vicious and unreasonable;
that when it is at the height, it masters us to that degree that a man's
reason can have no access," and instance our own experience in the act of
love,</p>
<p>"Quum jam praesagit gaudia corpus,<br/>
Atque in eo est Venus,<br/>
ut muliebria conserat arva."<br/>
<br/>
[None of the translators of the old editions used for this etext<br/>
have been willing to translate this passage from Lucretius, iv.<br/>
1099; they take a cop out by bashfully saying: "The sense is in the<br/>
preceding passage of the text." D.W.]<br/></p>
<p>wherein they conceive that the pleasure so transports us, that our reason
cannot perform its office, whilst we are in such ecstasy and rapture. I
know very well it may be otherwise, and that a man may sometimes, if he
will, gain this point over himself to sway his soul, even in the critical
moment, to think of something else; but then he must ply it to that bent.
I know that a man may triumph over the utmost effort of this pleasure: I
have experienced it in myself, and have not found Venus so imperious a
goddess, as many, and much more virtuous men than I, declare. I do not
consider it a miracle, as the Queen of Navarre does in one of the Tales of
her Heptameron—["Vu gentil liure pour son estoffe."]—(which is
a very pretty book of its kind), nor for a thing of extreme difficulty, to
pass whole nights, where a man has all the convenience and liberty he can
desire, with a long-coveted mistress, and yet be true to the pledge first
given to satisfy himself with kisses and suchlike endearments, without
pressing any further. I conceive that the example of the pleasure of the
chase would be more proper; wherein though the pleasure be less, there is
the higher excitement of unexpected joy, giving no time for the reason,
taken by surprise, to prepare itself for the encounter, when after a long
quest the beast starts up on a sudden in a place where, peradventure, we
least expected it; the shock and the ardour of the shouts and cries of the
hunters so strike us, that it would be hard for those who love this lesser
chase, to turn their thoughts upon the instant another way; and the poets
make Diana triumph over the torch and shafts of Cupid:</p>
<p>"Quis non malarum, quas amor curas habet,<br/>
Haec inter obliviscitur?"<br/>
<br/>
["Who, amongst such delights would not remove out of his thoughts<br/>
the anxious cares of love."—Horace, Epod., ii. 37.]<br/></p>
<p>To return to what I was saying before, I am tenderly compassionate of
others' afflictions, and should readily cry for company, if, upon any
occasion whatever, I could cry at all. Nothing tempts my tears but tears,
and not only those that are real and true, but whatever they are, feigned
or painted. I do not much lament the dead, and should envy them rather;
but I very much lament the dying. The savages do not so much offend me, in
roasting and eating the bodies of the dead, as they do who torment and
persecute the living. Nay, I cannot look so much as upon the ordinary
executions of justice, how reasonable soever, with a steady eye. Some one
having to give testimony of Julius Caesar's clemency; "he was," says he,
"mild in his revenges. Having compelled the pirates to yield by whom he
had before been taken prisoner and put to ransom; forasmuch as he had
threatened them with the cross, he indeed condemned them to it, but it was
after they had been first strangled. He punished his secretary Philemon,
who had attempted to poison him, with no greater severity than mere
death." Without naming that Latin author,—[Suetonius, Life of Casay,
c. 74.]—who thus dares to allege as a testimony of mercy the killing
only of those by whom we have been offended; it is easy to guess that he
was struck with the horrid and inhuman examples of cruelty practised by
the Roman tyrants.</p>
<p>For my part, even in justice itself, all that exceeds a simple death
appears to me pure cruelty; especially in us who ought, having regard to
their souls, to dismiss them in a good and calm condition; which cannot
be, when we have agitated them by insufferable torments. Not long since, a
soldier who was a prisoner, perceiving from a tower where he was shut up,
that the people began to assemble to the place of execution, and that the
carpenters were busy erecting a scaffold, he presently concluded that the
preparation was for him, and therefore entered into a resolution to kill
himself, but could find no instrument to assist him in his design except
an old rusty cart-nail that fortune presented to him; with this he first
gave himself two great wounds about his throat, but finding these would
not do, he presently afterwards gave himself a third in the belly, where
he left the nail sticking up to the head. The first of his keepers who
came in found him in this condition: yet alive, but sunk down and
exhausted by his wounds. To make use of time, therefore, before he should
die, they made haste to read his sentence; which having done, and he
hearing that he was only condemned to be beheaded, he seemed to take new
courage, accepted wine which he had before refused, and thanked his judges
for the unhoped-for mildness of their sentence; saying, that he had taken
a resolution to despatch himself for fear of a more severe and
insupportable death, having entertained an opinion, by the preparations he
had seen in the place, that they were resolved to torment him with some
horrible execution, and seemed to be delivered from death in having it
changed from what he apprehended.</p>
<p>I should advise that those examples of severity by which 'tis designed to
retain the people in their duty, might be exercised upon the dead bodies
of criminals; for to see them deprived of sepulture, to see them boiled
and divided into quarters, would almost work as much upon the vulgar, as
the pain they make the living endure; though that in effect be little or
nothing, as God himself says, "Who kill the body, and after that have no
more that they can do;"—[Luke, xii. 4.]—and the poets
singularly dwell upon the horrors of this picture, as something worse than
death:</p>
<p>"Heu! reliquias semiustas regis, denudatis ossibus,<br/>
Per terram sanie delibutas foede divexarier."<br/>
<br/>
["Alas! that the half-burnt remains of the king, exposing his bones,<br/>
should be foully dragged along the ground besmeared with gore."<br/>
—Cicero, Tusc. Quaes., i. 44.]<br/></p>
<p>I happened to come by one day accidentally at Rome, just as they were upon
executing Catena, a notorious robber: he was strangled without any emotion
of the spectators, but when they came to cut him in quarters, the hangman
gave not a blow that the people did not follow with a doleful cry and
exclamation, as if every one had lent his sense of feeling to the
miserable carcase. Those inhuman excesses ought to be exercised upon the
bark, and not upon the quick. Artaxerxes, in almost a like case, moderated
the severity of the ancient laws of Persia, ordaining that the nobility
who had committed a fault, instead of being whipped, as they were used to
be, should be stripped only and their clothes whipped for them; and that
whereas they were wont to tear off their hair, they should only take off
their high-crowned tiara.'—[Plutarch, Notable Sayings of the Ancient
King.]—The so devout Egyptians thought they sufficiently satisfied
the divine justice by sacrificing hogs in effigy and representation; a
bold invention to pay God so essential a substance in picture only and in
show.</p>
<p>I live in a time wherein we abound in incredible examples of this vice,
through the licence of our civil wars; and we see nothing in ancient
histories more extreme than what we have proof of every day, but I cannot,
any the more, get used to it. I could hardly persuade myself, before I saw
it with my eyes, that there could be found souls so cruel and fell, who,
for the sole pleasure of murder, would commit it; would hack and lop off
the limbs of others; sharpen their wits to invent unusual torments and new
kinds of death, without hatred, without profit, and for no other end but
only to enjoy the pleasant spectacle of the gestures and motions, the
lamentable groans and cries of a man dying in anguish. For this is the
utmost point to which cruelty can arrive:</p>
<p>"Ut homo hominem, non iratus, non timens,<br/>
tantum spectaturus, occidat."<br/>
<br/>
["That a man should kill a man, not being angry, not in fear, only<br/>
for the sake of the spectacle."—Seneca, Ep., 90.]<br/></p>
<p>For my own part, I cannot without grief see so much as an innocent beast
pursued and killed that has no defence, and from which we have received no
offence at all; and that which frequently happens, that the stag we hunt,
finding himself weak and out of breath, and seeing no other remedy,
surrenders himself to us who pursue him, imploring mercy by his tears:</p>
<p>"Questuque cruentus,<br/>
Atque imploranti similis,"<br/>
<br/>
["Who, bleeding, by his tears seems to crave mercy."<br/>
—AEnead, vii. 501.]<br/></p>
<p>has ever been to me a very unpleasing sight; and I hardly ever take a
beast alive that I do not presently turn out again. Pythagoras bought them
of fishermen and fowlers to do the same:</p>
<p>"Primoque a caede ferarum,<br/>
Incaluisse puto maculatum sanguine ferrum."<br/></p>
<p>["I think 'twas slaughter of wild beasts that first stained the<br/>
steel of man with blood."—Ovid, Met., xv. 106.]<br/></p>
<p>Those natures that are sanguinary towards beasts discover a natural
proneness to cruelty. After they had accustomed themselves at Rome to
spectacles of the slaughter of animals, they proceeded to those of the
slaughter of men, of gladiators. Nature has herself, I fear, imprinted in
man a kind of instinct to inhumanity; nobody takes pleasure in seeing
beasts play with and caress one another, but every one is delighted with
seeing them dismember, and tear one another to pieces. And that I may not
be laughed at for the sympathy I have with them, theology itself enjoins
us some favour in their behalf; and considering that one and the same
master has lodged us together in this palace for his service, and that
they, as well as we, are of his family, it has reason to enjoin us some
affection and regard to them. Pythagoras borrowed the metempsychosis from
the Egyptians; but it has since been received by several nations, and
particularly by our Druids:</p>
<p>"Morte carent animae; semperque, priore relicts<br/>
Sede, novis domibus vivunt, habitantque receptae."<br/>
<br/>
["Souls never die, but, having left their former seat, live<br/>
and are received into new homes."—Ovid, Met., xv. 158.]<br/></p>
<p>The religion of our ancient Gauls maintained that souls, being eternal,
never ceased to remove and shift their places from one body to another;
mixing moreover with this fancy some consideration of divine justice; for
according to the deportments of the soul, whilst it had been in Alexander,
they said that God assigned it another body to inhabit, more or less
painful, and proper for its condition:</p>
<p>"Muta ferarum<br/>
Cogit vincla pati; truculentos ingerit ursis,<br/>
Praedonesque lupis; fallaces vulpibus addit:<br/>
Atque ubi per varios annos, per mille figuras<br/>
<br/>
Egit, Lethaeo purgatos flumine, tandem<br/>
Rursus ad humanae revocat primordia formae:"<br/>
<br/>
["He makes them wear the silent chains of brutes, the bloodthirsty<br/>
souls he encloses in bears, the thieves in wolves, the deceivers in<br/>
foxes; where, after successive years and a thousand forms, man had<br/>
spent his life, and after purgation in Lethe's flood, at last he<br/>
restores them to the primordial human shapes."<br/>
—Claudian, In Ruf., ii. 482.]<br/></p>
<p>If it had been valiant, he lodged it in the body of a lion; if voluptuous,
in that of a hog; if timorous, in that of a hart or hare; if malicious, in
that of a fox, and so of the rest, till having purified it by this
chastisement, it again entered into the body of some other man:</p>
<p>"Ipse ego nam memini, Trojani, tempore belli<br/>
Panthoides Euphorbus eram."<br/>
<br/>
["For I myself remember that, in the days of the Trojan war, I was<br/>
Euphorbus, son of Pantheus."—Ovid, Met., xv. 160; and see Diogenes<br/>
Laertius, Life of Pythagoras.]<br/></p>
<p>As to the relationship betwixt us and beasts, I do not much admit of it;
nor of that which several nations, and those among the most ancient and
most noble, have practised, who have not only received brutes into their
society and companionship, but have given them a rank infinitely above
themselves, esteeming them one while familiars and favourites of the gods,
and having them in more than human reverence and respect; others
acknowledged no other god or divinity than they:</p>
<p>"Bellux a barbaris propter beneficium consecratae."<br/>
<br/>
["Beasts, out of opinion of some benefit received by them, were<br/>
consecrated by barbarians"—Cicero, De Natura Deor., i. 36.]<br/></p>
<p>"Crocodilon adorat<br/>
Pars haec; illa pavet saturam serpentibus ibin:<br/>
Effigies sacri hic nitet aurea cercopitheci;<br/>
Hic piscem flumints, illic<br/>
Oppida tota canem venerantur."<br/>
<br/>
["This place adores the crocodile; another dreads the ibis, feeder<br/>
on serpents; here shines the golden image of the sacred ape; here<br/>
men venerate the fish of the river; there whole towns worship a<br/>
dog."—Juvenal, xv. 2.]<br/></p>
<p>And the very interpretation that Plutarch, gives to this error, which is
very well conceived, is advantageous to them: for he says that it was not
the cat or the ox, for example, that the Egyptians adored: but that they,
in those beasts, adored some image of the divine faculties; in this,
patience and utility: in that, vivacity, or, as with our neighbours the
Burgundians and all the Germans, impatience to see themselves shut up; by
which they represented liberty, which they loved and adored above all
other godlike attributes, and so of the rest. But when, amongst the more
moderate opinions, I meet with arguments that endeavour to demonstrate the
near resemblance betwixt us and animals, how large a share they have in
our greatest privileges, and with how much probability they compare us
together, truly I abate a great deal of our presumption, and willingly
resign that imaginary sovereignty that is attributed to us over other
creatures.</p>
<p>But supposing all this were not true, there is nevertheless a certain
respect, a general duty of humanity, not only to beasts that have life and
sense, but even to trees, and plants. We owe justice to men, and
graciousness and benignity to other creatures that are capable of it;
there is a certain commerce and mutual obligation betwixt them and us. Nor
shall I be afraid to confess the tenderness of my nature so childish, that
I cannot well refuse to play with my dog, when he the most unseasonably
importunes me to do so. The Turks have alms and hospitals for beasts. The
Romans had public care to the nourishment of geese, by whose vigilance
their Capitol had been preserved. The Athenians made a decree that the
mules and moyls which had served at the building of the temple called
Hecatompedon should be free and suffered to pasture at their own choice,
without hindrance. The Agrigentines had a common use solemnly to inter the
beasts they had a kindness for, as horses of some rare quality, dogs, and
useful birds, and even those that had only been kept to divert their
children; and the magnificence that was ordinary with them in all other
things, also particularly appeared in the sumptuosity and numbers of
monuments erected to this end, and which remained in their beauty several
ages after. The Egyptians buried wolves, bears, crocodiles, dogs, and cats
in sacred places, embalmed their bodies, and put on mourning at their
death. Cimon gave an honourable sepulture to the mares with which he had
three times gained the prize of the course at the Olympic Games. The
ancient Xantippus caused his dog to be interred on an eminence near the
sea, which has ever since retained the name, and Plutarch says, that he
had a scruple about selling for a small profit to the slaughterer an ox
that had been long in his service.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />