<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0003" id="link2HCH0003"></SPAN></p>
<h2> CHAPTER III——THAT OUR AFFECTIONS CARRY THEMSELVES BEYOND US. </h2>
<p>Such as accuse mankind of the folly of gaping after future things, and
advise us to make our benefit of those which are present, and to set up
our rest upon them, as having no grasp upon that which is to come, even
less than that which we have upon what is past, have hit upon the most
universal of human errors, if that may be called an error to which nature
herself has disposed us, in order to the continuation of her own work,
prepossessing us, amongst several others, with this deceiving imagination,
as being more jealous of our action than afraid of our knowledge.</p>
<p>We are never present with, but always beyond ourselves: fear, desire,
hope, still push us on towards the future, depriving us, in the meantime,
of the sense and consideration of that which is to amuse us with the
thought of what shall be, even when we shall be no more.—[Rousseau,
Emile, livre ii.]</p>
<p>"Calamitosus est animus futuri auxius."<br/>
["The mind anxious about the future is unhappy."<br/>
—Seneca, Epist., 98.]<br/></p>
<p>We find this great precept often repeated in Plato, "Do thine own work,
and know thyself." Of which two parts, both the one and the other
generally, comprehend our whole duty, and do each of them in like manner
involve the other; for who will do his own work aright will find that his
first lesson is to know what he is, and that which is proper to himself;
and who rightly understands himself will never mistake another man's work
for his own, but will love and improve himself above all other things,
will refuse superfluous employments, and reject all unprofitable thoughts
and propositions. As folly, on the one side, though it should enjoy all it
desire, would notwithstanding never be content, so, on the other, wisdom,
acquiescing in the present, is never dissatisfied with itself. —[Cicero,
Tusc. Quae., 57, v. 18.]—Epicurus dispenses his sages from all
foresight and care of the future.</p>
<p>Amongst those laws that relate to the dead, I look upon that to be very
sound by which the actions of princes are to be examined after their
decease.—[Diodorus Siculus, i. 6.]— They are equals with, if
not masters of the laws, and, therefore, what justice could not inflict
upon their persons, 'tis but reason should be executed upon their
reputations and the estates of their successors—things that we often
value above life itself. 'Tis a custom of singular advantage to those
countries where it is in use, and by all good princes to be desired, who
have reason to take it ill, that the memories of the wicked should be used
with the same reverence and respect with their own. We owe subjection and
obedience to all our kings, whether good or bad, alike, for that has
respect unto their office; but as to esteem and affection, these are only
due to their virtue. Let us grant to political government to endure them
with patience, however unworthy; to conceal their vices; and to assist
them with our recommendation in their indifferent actions, whilst their
authority stands in need of our support. But, the relation of prince and
subject being once at an end, there is no reason we should deny the
expression of our real opinions to our own liberty and common justice, and
especially to interdict to good subjects the glory of having reverently
and faithfully served a prince, whose imperfections were to them so well
known; this were to deprive posterity of a useful example. And such as,
out of respect to some private obligation, unjustly espouse and vindicate
the memory of a faulty prince, do private right at the expense of public
justice. Livy does very truly say,—[xxxv. 48.]— "That the
language of men bred up in courts is always full of vain ostentation and
false testimony, every one indifferently magnifying his own master, and
stretching his commendation to the utmost extent of virtue and sovereign
grandeur." Some may condemn the freedom of those two soldiers who so
roundly answered Nero to his beard; the one being asked by him why he bore
him ill-will? "I loved thee," answered he, "whilst thou wert worthy of it,
but since thou art become a parricide, an incendiary, a player, and a
coachman, I hate thee as thou dost deserve." And the other, why he should
attempt to kill him? "Because," said he, "I could think of no other remedy
against thy perpetual mischiefs." —[Tacitus, Annal., xv. 67.]—But
the public and universal testimonies that were given of him after his
death (and so will be to all posterity, both of him and all other wicked
princes like him), of his tyrannies and abominable deportment, who, of a
sound judgment, can reprove them?</p>
<p>I am scandalised, that in so sacred a government as that of the
Lacedaemonians there should be mixed so hypocritical a ceremony at the
interment of their kings; where all their confederates and neighbours, and
all sorts and degrees of men and women, as well as their slaves, cut and
slashed their foreheads in token of sorrow, repeating in their cries and
lamentations that that king (let him have been as wicked as the devil) was
the best that ever they had;—[Herodotus, vi. 68.]—by this
means attributing to his quality the praise that only belongs to merit,
and that of right is due to supreme desert, though lodged in the lowest
and most inferior subject.</p>
<p>Aristotle, who will still have a hand in everything, makes a 'quaere' upon
the saying of Solon, that none can be said to be happy until he is dead:
"whether, then, he who has lived and died according to his heart's desire,
if he have left an ill repute behind him, and that his posterity be
miserable, can be said to be happy?" Whilst we have life and motion, we
convey ourselves by fancy and preoccupation, whither and to what we
please; but once out of being, we have no more any manner of communication
with that which is, and it had therefore been better said by Solon that
man is never happy, because never so, till he is no more.</p>
<p>"Quisquam<br/>
Vix radicitus e vita se tollit, et eicit;<br/>
Sed facit esse sui quiddam super inscius ipse,<br/>
Nec removet satis a projecto corpore sese, et<br/>
Vindicat."<br/>
["Scarcely one man can, even in dying, wholly detach himself from<br/>
the idea of life; in his ignorance he must needs imagine that there<br/>
is in him something that survives him, and cannot sufficiently<br/>
separate or emancipate himself from his remains"<br/>
—Lucretius, iii. 890.]<br/></p>
<p>Bertrand de Guesclin, dying at the siege of the Castle of Rancon, near
unto Puy, in Auvergne, the besieged were afterwards, upon surrender,
enjoined to lay down the keys of the place upon the corpse of the dead
general. Bartolommeo d'Alviano, the Venetian General, happening to die in
the service of the Republic in Brescia, and his corpse being to be carried
through the territory of Verona, an enemy's country, most of the army were
inclined to demand safe-conduct from the Veronese; but Theodoro Trivulzio
opposed the motion, rather choosing to make his way by force of arms, and
to run the hazard of a battle, saying it was by no means fit that he who
in his life was never afraid of his enemies should seem to apprehend them
when he was dead. In truth, in affairs of the same nature, by the Greek
laws, he who made suit to an enemy for a body to give it burial renounced
his victory, and had no more right to erect a trophy, and he to whom such
suit was made was reputed victor. By this means it was that Nicias lost
the advantage he had visibly obtained over the Corinthians, and that
Agesilaus, on the contrary, assured that which he had before very
doubtfully gained over the Boeotians.—[Plutarch, Life of Nicias, c.
ii.; Life of Agesilaus, c. vi.]</p>
<p>These things might appear strange, had it not been a general practice in
all ages not only to extend the concern of ourselves beyond this life,
but, moreover, to fancy that the favour of Heaven does not only very often
accompany us to the grave, but has also, even after life, a concern for
our ashes. Of which there are so many ancient examples (to say nothing of
those of our own observation), that it is not necessary I should longer
insist upon it. Edward I., King of England, having in the long wars
betwixt him and Robert, King of Scotland, had experience of how great
importance his own immediate presence was to the success of his affairs,
having ever been victorious in whatever he undertook in his own person,
when he came to die, bound his son in a solemn oath that, so soon as he
should be dead he should boil his body till the flesh parted from the
bones, and bury the flesh, reserving the bones to carry continually with
him in his army, so often as he should be obliged to go against the Scots,
as if destiny had inevitably attached victory, even to his remains. John
Zisca, the same who, to vindication of Wicliffe's heresies, troubled the
Bohemian state, left order that they should flay him after his death, and
of his skin make a drum to carry in the war against his enemies, fancying
it would contribute to the continuation of the successes he had always
obtained in the wars against them. In like manner certain of the Indians,
in their battles with the Spaniards, carried with them the bones of one of
their captains, in consideration of the victories they had formerly
obtained under his conduct. And other people of the same New World carry
about with them, in their wars, the relics of valiant men who have died in
battle, to incite their courage and advance their fortune. Of which
examples the first reserve nothing for the tomb but the reputation they
have acquired by their former achievements, but these attribute to them a
certain present and active power.</p>
<p>The proceeding of Captain Bayard is of a better composition, who finding
himself wounded to death with an harquebuss shot, and being importuned to
retire out of the fight, made answer that he would not begin at the last
gasp to turn his back to the enemy, and accordingly still fought on, till
feeling himself too faint and no longer able to sit on his horse, he
commanded his steward to set him down at the foot of a tree, but so that
he might die with his face towards the enemy, which he did.</p>
<p>I must yet add another example, equally remarkable for the present
consideration with any of the former. The Emperor Maximilian,
great-grandfather to the now King Philip,—[Philip II. of Spain.]—was
a prince endowed throughout with great and extraordinary qualities, and
amongst the rest with a singular beauty of person, but had withal a humour
very contrary to that of other princes, who for the despatch of their most
important affairs convert their close-stool into a chair of State, which
was, that he would never permit any of his bedchamber, how familiar
soever, to see him in that posture, and would steal aside to make water as
religiously as a virgin, shy to discover to his physician or any other
whomsoever those parts that we are accustomed to conceal. I myself, who
have so impudent a way of talking, am, nevertheless, naturally so modest
this way, that unless at the importunity of necessity or pleasure, I
scarcely ever communicate to the sight of any either those parts or
actions that custom orders us to conceal, wherein I suffer more constraint
than I conceive is very well becoming a man, especially of my profession.
But he nourished this modest humour to such a degree of superstition as to
give express orders in his last will that they should put him on drawers
so soon as he should be dead; to which, methinks, he would have done well
to have added that he should be blindfolded, too, that put them on. The
charge that Cyrus left with his children, that neither they, nor any
other, should either see or touch his body after the soul was departed
from it,—[Xenophon, Cyropedia, viii. 7.]—I attribute to some
superstitious devotion of his; for both his historian and himself, amongst
their great qualities, marked the whole course of their lives with a
singular respect and reverence to religion.</p>
<p>I was by no means pleased with a story, told me by a man of very great
quality of a relation of mine, and one who had given a very good account
of himself both in peace and war, that, coming to die in a very old age,
of excessive pain of the stone, he spent the last hours of his life in an
extraordinary solicitude about ordering the honour and ceremony of his
funeral, pressing all the men of condition who came to see him to engage
their word to attend him to his grave: importuning this very prince, who
came to visit him at his last gasp, with a most earnest supplication that
he would order his family to be there, and presenting before him several
reasons and examples to prove that it was a respect due to a man of his
condition; and seemed to die content, having obtained this promise, and
appointed the method and order of his funeral parade. I have seldom heard
of so persistent a vanity.</p>
<p>Another, though contrary curiosity (of which singularity, also, I do not
want domestic example), seems to be somewhat akin to this, that a man
shall cudgel his brains at the last moments of his life to contrive his
obsequies to so particular and unusual a parsimony as of one servant with
a lantern, I see this humour commended, and the appointment of Marcus.
Emilius Lepidus, who forbade his heirs to bestow upon his hearse even the
common ceremonies in use upon such occasions. Is it yet temperance and
frugality to avoid expense and pleasure of which the use and knowledge are
imperceptible to us? See, here, an easy and cheap reformation. If
instruction were at all necessary in this case, I should be of opinion
that in this, as in all other actions of life, each person should regulate
the matter according to his fortune; and the philosopher Lycon prudently
ordered his friends to dispose of his body where they should think most
fit, and as to his funeral, to order it neither too superfluous nor too
mean. For my part, I should wholly refer the ordering of this ceremony to
custom, and shall, when the time comes, accordingly leave it to their
discretion to whose lot it shall fall to do me that last office. "Totus
hic locus est contemnendus in nobis, non negligendus in nostris;"—["The
place of our sepulture is to be contemned by us, but not to be neglected
by our friends."—Cicero, Tusc. i. 45.]— and it was a holy
saying of a saint, "Curatio funeris, conditio sepultura: pompa exequiarum,
magis sunt vivorum solatia, quam subsidia mortuorum."—["The care of
death, the place of sepulture, the pomps of obsequies, are rather
consolations to the living than succours to the dead." August. De Civit.
Dei, i. 12.]—Which made Socrates answer Crito, who, at death, asked
him how he would be buried: "How you will," said he. "If I were to concern
myself beyond the present about this affair, I should be most tempted, as
the greatest satisfaction of this kind, to imitate those who in their
lifetime entertain themselves with the ceremony and honours of their own
obsequies beforehand, and are pleased with beholding their own dead
countenance in marble. Happy are they who can gratify their senses by
insensibility, and live by their death!"</p>
<p>I am ready to conceive an implacable hatred against all popular
domination, though I think it the most natural and equitable of all, so
oft as I call to mind the inhuman injustice of the people of Athens, who,
without remission, or once vouchsafing to hear what they had to say for
themselves, put to death their brave captains newly returned triumphant
from a naval victory they had obtained over the Lacedaemonians near the
Arginusian Isles, the most bloody and obstinate engagement that ever the
Greeks fought at sea; because (after the victory) they followed up the
blow and pursued the advantages presented to them by the rule of war,
rather than stay to gather up and bury their dead. And the execution is
yet rendered more odious by the behaviour of Diomedon, who, being one of
the condemned, and a man of most eminent virtue, political and military,
after having heard the sentence, advancing to speak, no audience till then
having been allowed, instead of laying before them his own cause, or the
impiety of so cruel a sentence, only expressed a solicitude for his
judges' preservation, beseeching the gods to convert this sentence to
their good, and praying that, for neglecting to fulfil the vows which he
and his companions had made (with which he also acquainted them) in
acknowledgment of so glorious a success, they might not draw down the
indignation of the gods upon them; and so without more words went
courageously to his death.</p>
<p>Fortune, a few years after, punished them in the same kind; for Chabrias,
captain-general of their naval forces, having got the better of Pollis,
Admiral of Sparta, at the Isle of Naxos, totally lost the fruits of his
victory, one of very great importance to their affairs, in order not to
incur the danger of this example, and so that he should not lose a few
bodies of his dead friends that were floating in the sea, gave opportunity
to a world of living enemies to sail away in safety, who afterwards made
them pay dear for this unseasonable superstition:—</p>
<p>"Quaeris, quo jaceas, post obitum, loco?<br/>
Quo non nata jacent."<br/>
["Dost ask where thou shalt lie after death?<br/>
Where things not born lie, that never being had."]<br/>
Seneca, Tyoa. Choro ii. 30.<br/></p>
<p>This other restores the sense of repose to a body without a soul:</p>
<p>"Neque sepulcrum, quo recipiatur, habeat: portum corporis, ubi,<br/>
remissa human, vita, corpus requiescat a malis."<br/>
["Nor let him have a sepulchre wherein he may be received, a haven<br/>
for his body, where, life being gone, that body may rest from its<br/>
woes."—Ennius, ap. Cicero, Tusc. i. 44.]<br/></p>
<p>As nature demonstrates to us that several dead things retain yet an occult
relation to life; wine changes its flavour and complexion in cellars,
according to the changes and seasons of the vine from whence it came; and
the flesh of—venison alters its condition in the powdering-tub, and
its taste according to the laws of the living flesh of its kind, as it is
said.</p>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />