<SPAN name="startofbook"></SPAN>
<div style="height: 8em;">
<br/><br/><br/><br/><br/><br/><br/><br/></div>
<h1> PROPOSED ROADS TO FREEDOM </h1>
<h2> By Bertrand Russell </h2>
<p><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><br/></p>
<p><b>CONTENTS</b></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_INTR"> INTRODUCTION </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_PART2"> PART I — HISTORICAL </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0001"> CHAPTER I — MARX AND SOCIALIST DOCTRINE</SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0002"> CHAPTER II — BAKUNIN AND ANARCHISM </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0003"> CHAPTER III — THE SYNDICALIST REVOLT </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_PART"> PART II — PROBLEMS OF THE FUTURE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0004"> CHAPTER IV — WORK AND PAY </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0005"> CHAPTER V — GOVERNMENT AND LAW </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0006"> CHAPTER VI — INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0007"> CHAPTER VII — SCIENCE AND ART UNDER
SOCIALISM </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2HCH0008"> CHAPTER VIII — THE WORLD AS IT COULD BE
MADE </SPAN></p>
<p><SPAN href="#link2H_FOOT"> FOOTNOTES: </SPAN></p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_INTR" id="link2H_INTR"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> INTRODUCTION </h2>
<p>THE attempt to conceive imaginatively a better ordering of human society
than the destructive and cruel chaos in which mankind has hitherto existed
is by no means modern: it is at least as old as Plato, whose "Republic"
set the model for the Utopias of subsequent philosophers. Whoever
contemplates the world in the light of an ideal—whether what he
seeks be intellect, or art, or love, or simple happiness, or all together—must
feel a great sorrow in the evils that men needlessly allow to continue,
and—if he be a man of force and vital energy—an urgent desire
to lead men to the realization of the good which inspires his creative
vision. It is this desire which has been the primary force moving the
pioneers of Socialism and Anarchism, as it moved the inventors of ideal
commonwealths in the past. In this there is nothing new. What is new in
Socialism and Anarchism, is that close relation of the ideal to the
present sufferings of men, which has enabled powerful political movements
to grow out of the hopes of solitary thinkers. It is this that makes
Socialism and Anarchism important, and it is this that makes them
dangerous to those who batten, consciously or unconsciously upon the evils
of our present order of society.</p>
<p>The great majority of men and women, in ordinary times, pass through life
without ever contemplating or criticising, as a whole, either their own
conditions or those of the world at large. They find themselves born into
a certain place in society, and they accept what each day brings forth,
without any effort of thought beyond what the immediate present requires.
Almost as instinctively as the beasts of the field, they seek the
satisfaction of the needs of the moment, without much forethought, and
without considering that by sufficient effort the whole conditions of
their lives could be changed. A certain percentage, guided by personal
ambition, make the effort of thought and will which is necessary to place
themselves among the more fortunate members of the community; but very few
among these are seriously concerned to secure for all the advantages which
they seek for themselves. It is only a few rare and exceptional men who
have that kind of love toward mankind at large that makes them unable to
endure patiently the general mass of evil and suffering, regardless of any
relation it may have to their own lives. These few, driven by sympathetic
pain, will seek, first in thought and then in action, for some way of
escape, some new system of society by which life may become richer, more
full of joy and less full of preventable evils than it is at present. But
in the past such men have, as a rule, failed to interest the very victims
of the injustices which they wished to remedy. The more unfortunate
sections of the population have been ignorant, apathetic from excess of
toil and weariness, timorous through the imminent danger of immediate
punishment by the holders of power, and morally unreliable owing to the
loss of self-respect resulting from their degradation. To create among
such classes any conscious, deliberate effort after general amelioration
might have seemed a hopeless task, and indeed in the past it has generally
proved so. But the modern world, by the increase of education and the rise
in the standard of comfort among wage-earners, has produced new
conditions, more favorable than ever before to the demand for radical
reconstruction. It is above all the Socialists, and in a lesser degree the
Anarchists (chiefly as the inspirers of Syndicalism), who have become the
exponents of this demand.</p>
<p>What is perhaps most remarkable in regard to both Socialism and Anarchism
is the association of a widespread popular movement with ideals for a
better world. The ideals have been elaborated, in the first instance, by
solitary writers of books, and yet powerful sections of the wage-earning
classes have accepted them as their guide in the practical affairs of the
world. In regard to Socialism this is evident; but in regard to Anarchism
it is only true with some qualification. Anarchism as such has never been
a widespread creed, it is only in the modified form of Syndicalism that it
has achieved popularity. Unlike Socialism and Anarchism, Syndicalism is
primarily the outcome, not of an idea, but of an organization: the fact of
Trade Union organization came first, and the ideas of Syndicalism are
those which seemed appropriate to this organization in the opinion of the
more advanced French Trade Unions. But the ideas are, in the main, derived
from Anarchism, and the men who gained acceptance for them were, for the
most part, Anarchists. Thus we may regard Syndicalism as the Anarchism of
the market-place as opposed to the Anarchism of isolated individuals which
had preserved a precarious life throughout the previous decades. Taking
this view, we find in Anarchist-Syndicalism the same combination of ideal
and organization as we find in Socialist political parties. It is from
this standpoint that our study of these movements will be undertaken.</p>
<p>Socialism and Anarchism, in their modern form, spring respectively from
two protagonists, Marx and Bakunin, who fought a lifelong battle,
culminating in a split in the first International. We shall begin our
study with these two men—first their teaching, and then the
organizations which they founded or inspired. This will lead us to the
spread of Socialism in more recent years, and thence to the Syndicalist
revolt against Socialist emphasis on the State and political action, and
to certain movements outside France which have some affinity with
Syndicalism— notably the I. W. W. in America and Guild Socialism in
England. From this historical survey we shall pass to the consideration of
some of the more pressing problems of the future, and shall try to decide
in what respects the world would be happier if the aims of Socialists or
Syndicalists were achieved.</p>
<p>My own opinion—which I may as well indicate at the outset—is
that pure Anarchism, though it should be the ultimate ideal, to which
society should continually approximate, is for the present impossible, and
would not survive more than a year or two at most if it were adopted. On
the other hand, both Marxian Socialism and Syndicalism, in spite of many
drawbacks, seem to me calculated to give rise to a happier and better
world than that in which we live. I do not, however, regard either of them
as the best practicable system. Marxian Socialism, I fear, would give far
too much power to the State, while Syndicalism, which aims at abolishing
the State, would, I believe, find itself forced to reconstruct a central
authority in order to put an end to the rivalries of different groups of
producers. The BEST practicable system, to my mind, is that of Guild
Socialism, which concedes what is valid both in the claims of the State
Socialists and in the Syndicalist fear of the State, by adopting a system
of federalism among trades for reasons similar to those which are
recommending federalism among nations. The grounds for these conclusions
will appear as we proceed.</p>
<p>Before embarking upon the history of recent movements In favor of radical
reconstruction, it will be worth while to consider some traits of
character which distinguish most political idealists, and are much
misunderstood by the general public for other reasons besides mere
prejudice. I wish to do full justice to these reasons, in order to show
the more effectually why they ought not to be operative.</p>
<p>The leaders of the more advanced movements are, in general, men of quite
unusual disinterestedness, as is evident from a consideration of their
careers. Although they have obviously quite as much ability as many men
who rise to positions of great power, they do not themselves become the
arbiters of contemporary events, nor do they achieve wealth or the
applause of the mass of their contemporaries. Men who have the capacity
for winning these prizes, and who work at least as hard as those who win
them, but deliberately adopt a line which makes the winning of them
impossible, must be judged to have an aim in life other than personal
advancement; whatever admixture of self-seeking may enter into the detail
of their lives, their fundamental motive must be outside Self. The
pioneers of Socialism, Anarchism, and Syndicalism have, for the most part,
experienced prison, exile, and poverty, deliberately incurred because they
would not abandon their propaganda; and by this conduct they have shown
that the hope which inspired them was not for themselves, but for mankind.</p>
<p>Nevertheless, though the desire for human welfare is what at bottom
determines the broad lines of such men's lives, it often happens that, in
the detail of their speech and writing, hatred is far more visible than
love. The impatient idealist—and without some impatience a man will
hardly prove effective—is almost sure to be led into hatred by the
oppositions and disappointments which he encounters in his endeavors to
bring happiness to the world. The more certain he is of the purity of his
motives and the truth of his gospel, the more indignant he will become
when his teaching is rejected. Often he will successfully achieve an
attitude of philosophic tolerance as regards the apathy of the masses, and
even as regards the whole-hearted opposition of professed defenders of the
status quo. But the men whom he finds it impossible to forgive are those
who profess the same desire for the amelioration of society as he feels
himself, but who do not accept his method of achieving this end. The
intense faith which enables him to withstand persecution for the sake of
his beliefs makes him consider these beliefs so luminously obvious that
any thinking man who rejects them must be dishonest, and must be actuated
by some sinister motive of treachery to the cause. Hence arises the spirit
of the sect, that bitter, narrow orthodoxy which is the bane of those who
hold strongly to an unpopular creed. So many real temptations to treachery
exist that suspicion is natural. And among leaders, ambition, which they
mortify in their choice of a career, is sure to return in a new form: in
the desire for intellectual mastery and for despotic power within their
own sect. From these causes it results that the advocates of drastic
reform divide themselves into opposing schools, hating each other with a
bitter hatred, accusing each other often of such crimes as being in the
pay of the police, and demanding, of any speaker or writer whom they are
to admire, that he shall conform exactly to their prejudices, and make all
his teaching minister to their belief that the exact truth is to be found
within the limits of their creed. The result of this state of mind is
that, to a casual and unimaginative attention, the men who have sacrificed
most through the wish to benefit mankind APPEAR to be actuated far more by
hatred than by love. And the demand for orthodoxy is stifling to any free
exercise of intellect. This cause, as well as economic prejudice, has made
it difficult for the "intellectuals" to co-operate prac- tically with the
more extreme reformers, however they may sympathize with their main
purposes and even with nine-tenths of their program.</p>
<p>Another reason why radical reformers are misjudged by ordinary men is that
they view existing society from outside, with hostility towards its
institutions. Although, for the most part, they have more belief than
their neighbors in human nature's inherent capacity for a good life, they
are so conscious of the cruelty and oppression resulting from existing
institutions that they make a wholly misleading impression of cynicism.
Most men have instinctively two entirely different codes of behavior: one
toward those whom they regard as companions or colleagues or friends, or
in some way members of the same "herd"; the other toward those whom they
regard as enemies or outcasts or a danger to society. Radical reformers
are apt to concentrate their attention upon the behavior of society toward
the latter class, the class of those toward whom the "herd" feels
ill-will. This class includes, of course, enemies in war, and criminals;
in the minds of those who consider the preservation of the existing order
essential to their own safety or privileges, it includes all who advocate
any great political or economic change, and all classes which, through
their poverty or through any other cause, are likely to feel a dangerous
degree of discontent. The ordinary citizen probably seldom thinks about
such individuals or classes, and goes through life believing that he and
his friends are kindly people, because they have no wish to injure those
toward whom they entertain no group-hostility. But the man whose attention
is fastened upon the relations of a group with those whom it hates or
fears will judge quite differently. In these relations a surprising
ferocity is apt to be developed, and a very ugly side of human nature
comes to the fore. The opponents of capitalism have learned, through the
study of certain historical facts, that this ferocity has often been shown
by the capitalists and by the State toward the wage-earning classes,
particularly when they have ventured to protest against the unspeakable
suffering to which industrialism has usually condemned them. Hence arises
a quite different attitude toward existing society from that of the
ordinary well-to-do citizen: an attitude as true as his, perhaps also as
untrue, but equally based on facts, facts concerning his relations to his
enemies instead of to his friends.</p>
<p>The class-war, like wars between nations, produces two opposing views,
each equally true and equally untrue. The citizen of a nation at war, when
he thinks of his own countrymen, thinks of them primarily as he has
experienced them, in dealings with their friends, in their family
relations, and so on. They seem to him on the whole kindly, decent folk.
But a nation with which his country is at war views his compatriots
through the medium of a quite different set of experiences: as they appear
in the ferocity of battle, in the invasion and subjugation of a hostile
territory, or in the chicanery of a juggling diplomacy. The men of whom
these facts are true are the very same as the men whom their compatriots
know as husbands or fathers or friends, but they are judged differently
because they are judged on different data. And so it is with those who
view the capitalist from the standpoint of the revolutionary wage-earner:
they appear inconceivably cynical and misjudging to the capitalist,
because the facts upon which their view is based are facts which he either
does not know or habitually ignores. Yet the view from the outside is just
as true as the view from the inside. Both are necessary to the complete
truth; and the Socialist, who emphasizes the outside view, is not a cynic,
but merely the friend of the wage-earners, maddened by the spectacle of
the needless misery which capitalism inflicts upon them.</p>
<p>I have placed these general reflections at the beginning of our study, in
order to make it clear to the reader that, whatever bitterness and hate
may be found in the movements which we are to examine, it is not
bitterness or hate, but love, that is their mainspring. It is difficult
not to hate those who torture the objects of our love. Though difficult,
it is not impossible; but it requires a breadth of outlook and a
comprehensiveness of understanding which are not easy to preserve amid a
desperate contest. If ultimate wisdom has not always been preserved by
Socialists and Anarchists, they have not differed in this from their
opponents; and in the source of their inspiration they have shown
themselves superior to those who acquiesce ignorantly or supinely in the
injustices and oppressions by which the existing system is preserved.</p>
<p><br/></p>
<h2> PROPOSED ROADS TO FREEDOM: SOCIALISM, ANARCHISM AND SYNDICALISM </h2>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_PART" id="link2H_PART"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> PART I — HISTORICAL </h2>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0001" id="link2HCH0001"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER I — MARX AND SOCIALIST DOCTRINE </h2>
<p>SOCIALISM, like everything else that is vital, is rather a tendency than a
strictly definable body of doctrine. A definition of Socialism is sure
either to include some views which many would regard as not Socialistic,
or to exclude others which claim to be included. But I think we shall come
nearest to the essence of Socialism by defining it as the advocacy of
communal ownership of land and capital. Communal ownership may mean
ownership by a democratic State, but cannot be held to include ownership
by any State which is not democratic. Communal ownership may also be
understood, as Anarchist Communism understands it, in the sense of
ownership by the free association of the men and women in a community
without those compulsory powers which are necessary to constitute a State.
Some Socialists expect communal ownership to arrive suddenly and
completely by a catastrophic revolution, while others expect it to come
gradually, first in one industry, then in another. Some insist upon the
necessity of completeness in the acquisition of land and capital by the
public, while others would be content to see lingering islands of private
ownership, provided they were not too extensive or powerful. What all
forms have in common is democracy and the abolition, virtual or complete,
of the present capitalistic system. The distinction between Socialists,
Anarchists and Syndicalists turns largely upon the kind of democracy which
they desire. Orthodox Socialists are content with parliamentary democracy
in the sphere of government, holding that the evils apparent in this form
of constitution at present would disappear with the disappearance of
capitalism. Anarchists and Syndicalists, on the other hand, object to the
whole parliamentary machinery, and aim at a different method of regulating
the political affairs of the community. But all alike are democratic in
the sense that they aim at abolishing every kind of privilege and every
kind of artificial inequality: all alike are champions of the wage- earner
in existing society. All three also have much in common in their economic
doctrine. All three regard capital and the wages system as a means of
exploiting the laborer in the interests of the possessing classes, and
hold that communal ownership, in one form or another, is the only means of
bringing freedom to the producers. But within the framework of this common
doctrine there are many divergences, and even among those who are strictly
to be called Socialists, there is a very considerable diversity of
schools.</p>
<p>Socialism as a power in Europe may be said to begin with Marx. It is true
that before his time there were Socialist theories, both in England and in
France. It is also true that in France, during the revolution of 1848,
Socialism for a brief period acquired considerable influence in the State.
But the Socialists who preceded Marx tended to indulge in Utopian dreams
and failed to found any strong or stable political party. To Marx, in
collaboration with Engels, are due both the formulation of a coherent body
of Socialist doctrine, sufficiently true or plausible to dominate the
minds of vast numbers of men, and the formation of the International
Socialist movement, which has continued to grow in all European countries
throughout the last fifty years.</p>
<p>In order to understand Marx's doctrine, it is necessary to know something
of the influences which formed his outlook. He was born in 1818 at Treves
in the Rhine Provinces, his father being a legal official, a Jew who had
nominally accepted Christianity. Marx studied jurisprudence, philosophy,
political economy and history at various German universities. In
philosophy he imbibed the doctrines of Hegel, who was then at the height
of his fame, and something of these doctrines dominated his thought
throughout his life. Like Hegel, he saw in history the development of an
Idea. He conceived the changes in the world as forming a logical
development, in which one phase passes by revolution into another, which
is its antithesis—a conception which gave to his views a certain
hard abstractness, and a belief in revolution rather than evolution. But
of Hegel's more definite doctrines Marx retained nothing after his youth.
He was recognized as a brilliant student, and might have had a prosperous
career as a professor or an official, but his interest in politics and his
Radical views led him into more arduous paths. Already in 1842 he became
editor of a newspaper, which was suppressed by the Prussian Government
early in the following year on account of its advanced opinions. This led
Marx to go to Paris, where he became known as a Socialist and acquired a
knowledge of his French predecessors.<SPAN href="#linknote-1"
name="linknoteref-1" id="linknoteref-1"><small>1</small></SPAN> Here in the
year 1844 began his lifelong friendship with Engels, who had been hitherto
in business in Manchester, where he had become acquainted with English
Socialism and had in the main adopted its doctrines.<SPAN href="#linknote-2"
name="linknoteref-2" id="linknoteref-2"><small>2</small></SPAN> In 1845 Marx
was expelled from Paris and went with Engels to live in Brussels. There he
formed a German Working Men's Association and edited a paper which was
their organ. Through his activities in Brussels he became known to the
German Communist League in Paris, who, at the end of 1847, invited him and
Engels to draw up for them a manifesto, which appeared in January, 1848.
This is the famous "Communist Manifesto," in which for the first time
Marx's system is set forth. It appeared at a fortunate moment. In the
following month, February, the revolution broke out in Paris, and in March
it spread to Germany. Fear of the revolution led the Brussels Government
to expel Marx from Belgium, but the German revolution made it possible for
him to return to his own country. In Germany he again edited a paper,
which again led him into a conflict with the authorities, increasing in
severity as the reaction gathered force. In June, 1849, his paper was
suppressed, and he was expelled from Prussia. He returned to Paris, but
was expelled from there also. This led him to settle in England—at
that time an asylum for friends of freedom—and in England, with only
brief intervals for purposes of agitation, he continued to live until his
death in 1883.</p>
<p>The bulk of his time was occupied in the composition of his great book,
"Capital."<SPAN href="#linknote-3" name="linknoteref-3" id="linknoteref-3"><small>3</small></SPAN>
His other important work during his later years was the formation and
spread of the International Working Men's Association. From 1849 onward
the greater part of his time was spent in the British Museum,
accumulating, with German patience, the materials for his terrific
indictment of capitalist society, but he retained his hold on the
International Socialist movement. In several countries he had sons-in-law
as lieutenants, like Napoleon's brothers, and in the various internal
contests that arose his will generally prevailed.</p>
<p>The most essential of Marx's doctrines may be reduced to three: first,
what is called the material- istic interpretation of history; second, the
law of the concentration of capital; and, third, the class-war.</p>
<p>1. The Materialistic Interpretation of History.— Marx holds that in
the main all the phenomena of human society have their origin in material
conditions, and these he takes to be embodied in economic systems.
Political constitutions, laws, religions, philosophies—all these he
regards as, in their broad outlines, expressions of the economic regime in
the society that gives rise to them. It would be unfair to represent him
as maintaining that the conscious economic motive is the only one of
importance; it is rather that economics molds character and opinion, and
is thus the prime source of much that appears in consciousness to have no
connection with them. He applies his doctrine in particular to two
revolutions, one in the past, the other in the future. The revolution in
the past is that of the bourgeoisie against feudalism, which finds its
expression, according to him, particularly in the French Revolution. The
one in the future is the revolution of the wage- earners, or proletariat,
against the bourgeoisie, which is to establish the Socialist Commonwealth.
The whole movement of history is viewed by him as necessary, as the effect
of material causes operating upon human beings. He does not so much
advocate the Socialist revolution as predict it. He holds, it is true,
that it will be beneficent, but he is much more concerned to prove that it
must inevitably come. The same sense of necessity is visible in his
exposition of the evils of the capitalist system. He does not blame
capitalists for the cruelties of which he shows them to have been guilty;
he merely points out that they are under an inherent necessity to behave
cruelly so long as private ownership of land and capital continues. But
their tyranny will not last forever, for it generates the forces that must
in the end overthrow it.</p>
<p>2. The Law of the Concentration of Capital.— Marx pointed out that
capitalist undertakings tend to grow larger and larger. He foresaw the
substitution of trusts for free competition, and predicted that the number
of capitalist enterprises must diminish as the magnitude of single
enterprises increased. He supposed that this process must involve a
diminution, not only in the number of businesses, but also in the number
of capitalists. Indeed, he usually spoke as though each business were
owned by a single man. Accordingly, he expected that men would be
continually driven from the ranks of the capitalists into those of the
proletariat, and that the capitalists, in the course of time, would grow
numerically weaker and weaker. He applied this principle not only to
industry but also to agriculture. He expected to find the landowners
growing fewer and fewer while their estates grew larger and larger. This
process was to make more and more glaring the evils and injustices of the
capitalist system, and to stimulate more and more the forces of
opposition.</p>
<p>3. The Class War.—Marx conceives the wage- earner and the capitalist
in a sharp antithesis. He imagines that every man is, or must soon become,
wholly the one or wholly the other. The wage- earner, who possesses
nothing, is exploited by the capitalists, who possess everything. As the
capitalist system works itself out and its nature becomes more clear, the
opposition of bourgeoisie and proletariat becomes more and more marked.
The two classes, since they have antagonistic interests, are forced into a
class war which generates within the capitalist regime internal forces of
disruption. The working men learn gradually to combine against their
exploiters, first locally, then nationally, and at last internationally.
When they have learned to combine internationally they must be victorious.
They will then decree that all land and capital shall be owned in common;
exploitation will cease; the tyranny of the owners of wealth will no
longer be possible; there will no longer be any division of society into
classes, and all men will be free.</p>
<p>All these ideas are already contained in the "Communist Manifesto," a work
of the most amazing vigor and force, setting forth with terse compression
the titanic forces of the world, their epic battle, and the inevitable
consummation. This work is of such importance in the development of
Socialism and gives such an admirable statement of the doctrines set forth
at greater length and with more pedantry in "Capital," that its salient
passages must be known by anyone who wishes to understand the hold which
Marxian Socialism has acquired over the intellect and imagination of a
large proportion of working-class leaders.</p>
<p>"A spectre is haunting Europe," it begins, "the spectre of Communism. All
the Powers of old Europe have entered into a holy alliance to exorcise
this spectre—Pope and Czar, Metternich and Guizot, French Radicals
and German police-spies. Where is the party in opposition that has not
been decried as communistic by its opponents in power? Where the
Opposition that has not hurled back the branding reproach of Communism
against the more advanced opposition parties, as well as against its
re-actionary adversaries?"</p>
<p>The existence of a class war is nothing new: "The history of all hitherto
existing society is the history of class struggles." In these struggles
the fight "each time ended, either in a revolutionary re-constitution of
society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending classes."</p>
<p>"Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeoisie . . . has simplified the class
antagonisms. Society as a whole is more and more splitting up into two
great hostile camps, into two great classes directly facing each other:
Bourgeoisie and Proletariat." Then follows a history of the fall of
feudalism, leading to a description of the bourgeoisie as a revolutionary
force. "The bourgeoisie, historically, has played a most revolutionary
part." "For exploitation, veiled by religious and political illusions, it
has substituted naked, shameless, direct, brutal exploitation." "The need
of a constantly expanding market for its products chases the bourgeoisie
over the whole surface of the globe." "The bourgeoisie, during its rule of
scarce one hundred years, has created more massive and more colossal
productive forces than have all preceding generations together." Feudal
relations became fetters: "They had to be burst asunder; they were burst
asunder. . . . A similar movement is going on before our own eyes." "The
weapons with which the bourgeoisie felled feudalism to the ground are now
turned against the bourgeoisie itself. But not only has the bourgoisie
forged the weapons that bring death to itself; it has also called into
existence the men who are to wield those weapons— the modern working
class—the proletarians."</p>
<p>The cause of the destitution of the proletariat are then set forth. "The
cost of production of a workman is restricted, almost entirely, to the
means of subsistence that he requires for his maintenance and for the
propagation of his race. But the price of a commodity, and therefore also
of labor, is equal to its cost of production. In proportion, therefore, as
the repulsiveness of the work increases, the wage decreases. Nay more, in
proportion as the use of machinery and diversion of labor increases, in
the same proportion the burden of toil also increases."</p>
<p>"Modern industry has converted the little workshop of the patriarchal
master into the great factory of the industrial capitalist. Masses of
laborers, crowded into the factory, are organized like soldiers. As
privates of the industrial army they are placed under the command of a
perfect hierarchy of officers and sergeants. Not only are they slaves of
the bourgeois class, and of the bourgeois State, they are daily and hourly
enslaved by the machine, by the over-looker, and, above all, by the
individual bourgeois manufacturer himself. The more openly this despotism
proclaims gain to be its end and aim, the more petty, the more hateful,
and the more embittering it is."</p>
<p>The Manifesto tells next the manner of growth of the class struggle. "The
proletariat goes through various stages of development. With its birth
begins its struggle with the bourgeoisie. At first the contest is carried
on by individual laborers, then by the workpeople of a factory, then by
the operatives of one trade, in one locality, against the individual
bourgeois who directly exploits them. They direct their attacks not
against the bourgeois conditions of production, but against the
instruments of production themselves."</p>
<p>"At this stage the laborers still form an incoherent mass scattered over
the whole country, and broken up by their mutual competition. If anywhere
they unite to form more compact bodies, this is not yet the consequence of
their own active union, but of the union of the bourgeoisie, which class,
in order to attain its own political ends, is compelled to set the whole
proletariat in motion, and is moreover yet, for a time, able to do so."</p>
<p>"The collisions between individual workmen and individual bourgeois take
more and more the character of collisions between two classes. Thereupon
the workers begin to form combinations (Trades Unions) against the
bourgeois; they club together in order to keep up the rate of wages; they
found permanent associations in order to make provision beforehand for
these occasional revolts. Here and there the contest breaks out into
riots. Now and then the workers are victorious, but only for a time. The
real fruit of their battles lies, not in the immediate result, but in the
ever-expanding union of the workers. This union is helped on by the im-
proved means of communication that are created by modern industry, and
that place the workers of different localities in contact with one
another. It was just this contact that was needed to centralize the
numerous local struggles, all of the same character, into one national
struggle between classes. But every class struggle is a political
struggle. And that union, to attain which the burghers of the Middle Ages,
with their miserable highways, required centuries, the modern
proletarians, thanks to railways, achieve in a few years. This
organization of the proletarians into a class, and consequently into a
political party, is continually being upset again by the competition
between the workers themselves. But it ever rises up again, stronger,
firmer, mightier. It compels legislative recognition of particular
interests of the workers, by taking advantage of the divisions among the
bourgeoisie itself."</p>
<p>"In the conditions of the proletariat, those of old society at large are
already virtually swamped. The proletarian is without property; his
relation to his wife and children has no longer anything in common with
the bourgeois family-relations; modern industrial labor, modern subjection
to capital, the same in England as in France, in America as in Germany,
has stripped him of every trace of national character. Law, morality,
religion, are to him so many bourgeois prejudices, behind which lurk in
ambush just as many bourgeois interests. All the preceding classes that
got the upper hand, sought to fortify their already acquired status by
subjecting society at large to their conditions of appropriation. The
proletarians cannot become masters of the productive forces of society,
except by abolishing their own previous mode of appropriation, and thereby
also every other previous mode of appropriation. They have nothing of
their own to secure and to fortify; their mission is to destroy all
previous securities for, and insurances of, individual property. All
previous historical movements were movements of minorities, or in the
interest of minorities. The proletarian movement is the self-conscious,
independent movement of the immense majority, in the interest of the
immense majority. The proletariat, the lowest stratum of our present
society, cannot stir, cannot raise itself up, without the whole super-
incumbent strata of official society being sprung into the air."</p>
<p>The Communists, says Marx, stand for the proletariat as a whole. They are
international. "The Communists are further reproached with desiring to
abolish countries and nationality. The working men have no country. We
cannot take from them what they have not got."</p>
<p>The immediate aim of the Communists is the conquests of political power by
the proletariat. "The theory of the Communists may be summed up in the
single sentence: Abolition of private property."</p>
<p>The materialistic interpretation of history is used to answer such charges
as that Communism is anti-Christian. "The charges against Communism made
from a religious, a philosophical, and, generally, from an ideological
standpoint, are not deserving of serious examination. Does it require deep
intuition to comprehend that man's ideas, views and conceptions, in one
word, man's consciousness, changes with every change in the conditions of
his material existence, in his social relations, and in his social life?"</p>
<p>The attitude of the Manifesto to the State is not altogether easy to
grasp. "The executive of the modern State," we are told, "is but a
Committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie."
Nevertheless, the first step for the proletariat must be to acquire
control of the State. "We have seen above, that the first step in the
revolution by the working class, is to raise the proletariat to the
position of ruling class, to win the battle of democracy. The proletariat
will use its political supremacy to wrest, by degrees, all capital from
the bourgeoisie, to centralize all instruments of production in the hands
of the State, i.e., of the proletariat organized as the ruling class; and
to increase the total of productive forces as rapidly as possible."</p>
<p>The Manifesto passes on to an immediate program of reforms, which would in
the first instance much increase the power of the existing State, but it
is contended that when the Socialist revolution is accomplished, the
State, as we know it, will have ceased to exist. As Engels says elsewhere,
when the proletariat seizes the power of the State "it puts an end to all
differences of class and antagonisms of class, and consequently also puts
an end to the State as a State." Thus, although State Socialism might, in
fact, be the outcome of the proposals of Marx and Engels, they cannot
themselves be accused of any glorification of the State.</p>
<p>The Manifesto ends with an appeal to the wage- earners of the world to
rise on behalf of Communism. "The Communists disdain to conceal their
views and aims. They openly declare that their ends can be attained only
by the forcible overthrow of all existing social conditions. Let the
ruling classes tremble at a Communistic revolution. The proletarians have
nothing to lose but their chains. They have a world to win. Working men of
all countries, unite!"</p>
<p>In all the great countries of the Continent, except Russia, a revolution
followed quickly on the publication of the Communist Manifesto, but the
revolution was not economic or international, except at first in France.
Everywhere else it was inspired by the ideas of nationalism. Accordingly,
the rulers of the world, momentarily terrified, were able to recover power
by fomenting the enmities inherent in the nationalist idea, and
everywhere, after a very brief triumph, the revolution ended in war and
reaction. The ideas of the Communist Manifesto appeared before the world
was ready for them, but its authors lived to see the beginnings of the
growth of that Socialist movement in every country, which has pressed on
with increasing force, influencing Governments more and more, dominating
the Russian Revolution, and perhaps capable of achieving at no very
distant date that international triumph to which the last sentences of the
Manifesto summon the wage-earners of the world.</p>
<p>Marx's magnum opus, "Capital," added bulk and substance to the theses of
the Communist Manifesto. It contributed the theory of surplus value, which
professed to explain the actual mechanism of capitalist exploitation. This
doctrine is very complicated and is scarcely tenable as a contribution to
pure theory. It is rather to be viewed as a translation into abstract
terms of the hatred with which Marx regarded the system that coins wealth
out of human lives, and it is in this spirit, rather than in that of
disinterested analysis, that it has been read by its admirers. A critical
examination of the theory of surplus value would require much difficult
and abstract discussion of pure economic theory without having much
bearing upon the practical truth or falsehood of Socialism; it has
therefore seemed impossible within the limits of the present volume. To my
mind the best parts of the book are those which deal with economic facts,
of which Marx's knowledge was encyclopaedic. It was by these facts that he
hoped to instil into his disciples that firm and undying hatred that
should make them soldiers to the death in the class war. The facts which
he accumulates are such as are practically unknown to the vast majority of
those who live comfortable lives. They are very terrible facts, and the
economic system which generates them must be acknowledged to be a very
terrible system. A few examples of his choice of facts will serve to
explain the bitterness of many Socialists:—</p>
<p>Mr. Broughton Charlton, county magistrate, declared, as chairman of a
meeting held at the Assembly Rooms, Nottingham, on the 14th January, 1860,
"that there was an amount of privation and suffering among that portion of
the population connected with the lace trade, unknown in other parts of
the kingdom, indeed, in the civilized world. . . . Children of nine or ten
years are dragged from their squalid beds at two, three, or four o clock
in the morning and compelled to work for a bare subsistence until ten,
eleven, or twelve at night, their limbs wearing away, their frames
dwindling, their faces whitening, and their humanity absolutely sinking
into a stone-like torpor, utterly horrible to contemplate."<SPAN href="#linknote-4" name="linknoteref-4" id="linknoteref-4"><small>4</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Three railway men are standing before a London coroner's jury—a
guard, an engine-driver, a signalman. A tremendous railway accident has
hurried hundreds of passengers into another world. The negligence of the
employes is the cause of the misfortune. They declare with one voice
before the jury that ten or twelve years before, their labor only lasted
eight hours a day. During the last five or six years it had been screwed
up to 14, 18, and 20 hours, and under a specially severe pressure of
holiday-makers, at times of excursion trains, it often lasted 40 or 50
hours without a break. They were ordinary men, not Cyclops. At a certain
point their labor-power failed. Torpor seized them. Their brain ceased to
think, their eyes to see. The thoroughly "respectable" British jurymen
answered by a verdict that sent them to the next assizes on a charge of
manslaughter, and, in a gentle "rider" to their verdict, expressed the
pious hope that the capitalistic magnates of the railways would, in
future, be more extravagant in the purchase of a sufficient quantity of
labor-power, and more "abstemious," more "self-denying," more "thrifty,"
in the draining of paid labor-power.<SPAN href="#linknote-5"
name="linknoteref-5" id="linknoteref-5"><small>5</small></SPAN></p>
<p>In the last week of June, 1863, all the London daily papers published a
paragraph with the "sensational" heading, "Death from simple over-work."
It dealt with the death of the milliner, Mary Anne Walkley, 20 years of
age, employed in a highly respectable dressmaking establishment, exploited
by a lady with the pleasant name of Elise. The old, often-told story was
once more recounted. This girl worked, on an average, 16 1/2 hours, during
the season often 30 hours, without a break, whilst her failing labor-power
was revived by occasional supplies of sherry, port, or coffee. It was just
now the height of the season. It was necessary to conjure up in the
twinkling of an eye the gorgeous dresses for the noble ladies bidden to
the ball in honor of the newly- imported Princess of Wales. Mary Anne
Walkley had worked without intermission for 26 1/2 hours, with 60 other
girls, 30 in one room, that only afforded 1/3 of the cubic feet of air
required for them. At night, they slept in pairs in one of the stifling
holes into which the bedroom was divided by partitions of board. And this
was one of the best millinery establishments in London. Mary Anne Walkley
fell ill on the Friday, died on Sunday, without, to the astonishment of
Madame Elise, having previously completed the work in hand. The doctor,
Mr. Keys, called too late to the death bed, duly bore witness before the
coroner's jury that "Mary Anne Walkley had died from long hours of work in
an over- crowded workroom, and a too small and badly ventilated bedroom."
In order to give the doctor a lesson in good manners, the coroner's jury
thereupon brought in a verdict that "the deceased had died of apoplexy,
but there was reason to fear that her death had been accelerated by
over-work in an over-crowded workroom, &c." "Our white slaves," cried
the "Morning Star," the organ of the free-traders, Cobden and Bright, "our
white slaves, who are toiled into the grave, for the most part silently
pine and die."<SPAN href="#linknote-6" name="linknoteref-6" id="linknoteref-6"><small>6</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Edward VI: A statue of the first year of his reign, 1547, ordains that if
anyone refuses to work, he shall be condemned as a slave to the person who
has denounced him as an idler. The master shall feed his slave on bread
and water, weak broth and such refuse meat as he thinks fit. He has the
right to force him to do any work, no matter how disgusting, with whip and
chains. If the slave is absent a fortnight, he is condemned to slavery for
life and is to be branded on forehead or back with the letter S; if he
runs away thrice, he is to be executed as a felon. The master can sell
him, bequeath him, let him out on hire as a slave, just as any other
personal chattel or cattle. If the slaves attempt anything against the
masters, they are also to be executed. Justices of the peace, on
information, are to hunt the rascals down. If it happens that a vagabond
has been idling about for three days, he is to be taken to his birthplace,
branded with a redhot iron with the letter V on the breast and be set to
work, in chains, in the streets or at some other labor. If the vagabond
gives a false birthplace, he is then to become the slave for life of this
place, of its inhabitants, or its corporation, and to be branded with an
S. All persons have the right to take away the children of the vagabonds
and to keep them as apprentices, the young men until the 24th year, the
girls until the 20th. If they run away, they are to become up to this age
the slaves of their masters, who can put them in irons, whip them, &c.,
if they like. Every master may put an iron ring around the neck, arms or
legs of his slave, by which to know him more easily and to be more certain
of him. The last part of this statute provides that certain poor people
may be employed by a place or by persons, who are willing to give them
food and drink and to find them work. This kind of parish-slaves was kept
up in England until far into the 19th century under the name of
"roundsmen."<SPAN href="#linknote-7" name="linknoteref-7" id="linknoteref-7"><small>7</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Page after page and chapter after chapter of facts of this nature, each
brought up to illustrate some fatalistic theory which Marx professes to
have proved by exact reasoning, cannot but stir into fury any passionate
working-class reader, and into unbearable shame any possessor of capital
in whom generosity and justice are not wholly extinct.</p>
<p>Almost at the end of the volume, in a very brief chapter, called
"Historical Tendency of Capitalist Accumulation," Marx allows one moment's
glimpse of the hope that lies beyond the present horror:—</p>
<p>As soon as this process of transformation has sufficiently decomposed the
old society from top to bottom, as soon as the laborers are turned into
proletarians, their means of labor into capital, as soon as the capitalist
mode of production stands on its own feet, then the further socialization
of labor and further transformation of the land and other means of
production into so- cially exploited and, therefore, common means of
production, as well as the further expropriation of private proprietors,
takes a new form. That which is now to be expropriated is no longer the
laborer working for himself, but the capitalist exploiting many laborers.
This expropriation is accomplished by the action of the immanent laws of
capitalistic production itself, by the centralization of capital. One
capitalist always kills many, and in hand with this centralization, or
this expropriation of many capitalists by few, develop, on an ever
extending scale, the co-operative form of the labor-process, the conscious
technical application of science, the methodical cultivation of the soil,
the transformation of the instruments of labor into instruments of labor
only usable in common, the economizing of all means of production by their
use as the means of production of combined, socialized labor, the
entanglement of all peoples in the net of the world-market, and with this,
the international character of the capitalistic regime. Along with the
constantly diminishing number of the magnates of capital, who usurp and
monopolize all advantages of this process of transformation, grows the
mass of misery, oppression, slavery, degradation, exploitation; but with
this, too, grows the revolt of the working- class, a class always
increasing in numbers, and disciplined, united, organized by the very
mechanism of the process of capitalist production itself. The monopoly of
capital becomes a fetter upon the mode of production, which has sprung up
and flourished along with, and under it. Centralization of the means of
production and socialization of labor at last reach a point where they
become incompatible with their capitalist integument. This integument is
burst asunder. The knell of capitalist private property sounds. The
expropriators are expropriated,<SPAN href="#linknote-8" name="linknoteref-8" id="linknoteref-8"><small>8</small></SPAN></p>
<p>That is all. Hardly another word from beginning to end is allowed to
relieve the gloom, and in this relentless pressure upon the mind of the
reader lies a great part of the power which this book has acquired.</p>
<p>Two questions are raised by Marx's work: First, Are his laws of historical
development true? Second, Is Socialism desirable? The second of these
questions is quite independent of the first. Marx professes to prove that
Socialism must come, but scarcely concerns himself to argue that when it
comes it will be a good thing. It may be, however, that if it comes, it
will be a good thing, even though all Marx's arguments to prove that it
must come should be at fault. In actual fact, time has shown many flaws in
Marx's theories. The development of the world has been sufficiently like
his prophecy to prove him a man of very unusual penetration, but has not
been sufficiently like to make either political or economic history
exactly such as he predicted that it would be. Nationalism, so far from
diminishing, has increased, and has failed to be conquered by the
cosmopolitan tendencies which Marx rightly discerned in finance. Although
big businesses have grown bigger and have over a great area reached the
stage of monopoly, yet the number of shareholders in such enterprises is
so large that the actual number of individuals interested in the
capitalist system has continually increased. Moreover, though large firms
have grown larger, there has been a simultaneous increase in firms of
medium size. Meanwhile the wage-earners, who were, according to Marx, to
have remained at the bare level of subsistence at which they were in the
England of the first half of the nineteenth century, have instead profited
by the general increase of wealth, though in a lesser degree than the
capitalists. The supposed iron law of wages has been proved untrue, so far
as labor in civilized countries is concerned. If we wish now to find
examples of capitalist cruelty analogous to those with which Marx's book
is filled, we shall have to go for most of our material to the Tropics, or
at any rate to regions where there are men of inferior races to exploit.
Again: the skilled worker of the present day is an aristocrat in the world
of labor. It is a question with him whether he shall ally himself with the
unskilled worker against the capitalist, or with the capitalist against
the unskilled worker. Very often he is himself a capitalist in a small
way, and if he is not so individually, his trade union or his friendly
society is pretty sure to be so. Hence the sharpness of the class war has
not been maintained. There are gradations, intermediate ranks between rich
and poor, instead of the clear-cut logical antithesis between the workers
who have nothing and the capitalists who have all. Even in Germany, which
became the home of orthodox Marxianism and developed a powerful
Social-Democratic party, nominally accepting the doctrine of "Das Kapital"
as all but verbally inspired, even there the enormous increase of wealth
in all classes in the years preceding the war led Socialists to revise
their beliefs and to adopt an evolutionary rather than a revolutionary
attitude. Bernstein, a German Socialist who lived long in England,
inaugurated the "Revisionist" movement which at last conquered the bulk of
the party. His criticisms of Marxian orthodoxy are set forth in his
"Evolutionary Socialism."<SPAN href="#linknote-9" name="linknoteref-9" id="linknoteref-9"><small>9</small></SPAN> Bernstein's work, as is common in
Broad Church writers, consists largely in showing that the Founders did
not hold their doctrines so rigidly as their followers have done. There is
much in the writings of Marx and Engels that cannot be fitted into the
rigid orthodoxy which grew up among their disciples. Bernstein's main
criticisms of these disciples, apart from such as we have already
mentioned, consist in a defense of piecemeal action as against revolution.
He protests against the attitude of undue hostility to Liberalism which is
common among Socialists, and he blunts the edge of the Internationalism
which undoubtedly is part of the teachings of Marx. The workers, he says,
have a Fatherland as soon as they become citizens, and on this basis he
defends that degree of nationalism which the war has since shown to be
prevalent in the ranks of Socialists. He even goes so far as to maintain
that European nations have a right to tropical territory owing to their
higher civilization. Such doctrines diminish revolutionary ardor and tend
to transform Socialists into a left wing of the Liberal Party. But the
increasing prosperity of wage-earners before the war made these
developments inevitable. Whether the war will have altered conditions in
this respect, it is as yet impossible to know. Bernstein concludes with
the wise remark that: "We have to take working men as they are. And they
are neither so universally paupers as was set out in the Communist
Manifesto, nor so free from prejudices and weaknesses as their courtiers
wish to make us believe."</p>
<p>In March, 1914, Bernstein delivered a lecture in Budapest in which he
withdrew from several of the positions he had taken up (vide Budapest
"Volkstimme," March 19, 1914).</p>
<p>Berstein represents the decay of Marxian orthodoxy from within.
Syndicalism represents an attack against it from without, from the
standpoint of a doctrine which professes to be even more radical and more
revolutionary than that of Marx and Engels. The attitude of Syndicalists
to Marx may be seen in Sorel's little book, "La Decomposition du
Marxisme," and in his larger work, "Reflections on Violence," authorized
translation by T. E. Hulme (Allen & Unwin, 1915). After quoting
Bernstein, with approval in so far as he criticises Marx, Sorel proceeds
to other criticisms of a different order. He points out (what is true)
that Marx's theoretical economics remain very near to Manchesterism: the
orthodox political economy of his youth was accepted by him on many points
on which it is now known to be wrong. According to Sorel, the really
essential thing in Marx's teaching is the class war. Whoever keeps this
alive is keeping alive the spirit of Socialism much more truly than those
who adhere to the letter of Social-Democratic orthodoxy. On the basis of
the class war, French Syndicalists developed a criticism of Marx which
goes much deeper than those that we have been hitherto considering. Marx's
views on historical development may have been in a greater or less degree
mistaken in fact, and yet the economic and political system which he
sought to create might be just as desirable as his followers suppose.
Syndicalism, however, criticises, not only Marx's views of fact, but also
the goal at which he aims and the general nature of the means which he
recommends. Marx's ideas were formed at a time when democracy did not yet
exist. It was in the very year in which "Das Kapital" appeared that urban
working men first got the vote in England and universal suffrage was
granted by Bismarck in Northern Germany. It was natural that great hopes
should be entertained as to what democracy would achieve. Marx, like the
orthodox economists, imagined that men's opinions are guided by a more or
less enlightened view of economic self-interest, or rather of economic
class interest. A long experience of the workings of political democracy
has shown that in this respect Disraeli and Bismarck were shrewder judges
of human nature than either Liberals or Socialists. It has become
increasingly difficult to put trust in the State as a means to liberty, or
in political parties as instruments sufficiently powerful to force the
State into the service of the people. The modern State, says Sorel, "is a
body of intellectuals, which is invested with privileges, and which
possesses means of the kind called political for defending itself against
the attacks made on it by other groups of intellectuals, eager to possess
the profits of public employment. Parties are constituted in order to
acquire the conquest of these employments, and they are analogous to the
State."<SPAN href="#linknote-10" name="linknoteref-10" id="linknoteref-10"><small>10</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Syndicalists aim at organizing men, not by party, but by occupation. This,
they say, alone represents the true conception and method of the class
war. Accordingly they despise all POLITICAL action through the medium of
Parliament and elections: the kind of action that they recommend is direct
action by the revolutionary syndicate or trade union. The battle- cry of
industrial versus political action has spread far beyond the ranks of
French Syndicalism. It is to be found in the I. W. W. in America, and
among Industrial Unionists and Guild Socialists in Great Britain. Those
who advocate it, for the most part, aim also at a different goal from that
of Marx. They believe that there can be no adequate individual freedom
where the State is all-powerful, even if the State be a Socialist one.
Some of them are out-and- out Anarchists, who wish to see the State wholly
abolished; others only wish to curtail its authority. Owing to this
movement, opposition to Marx, which from the Anarchist side existed from
the first, has grown very strong. It is this opposition in its older form
that will occupy us in our next chapter.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0002" id="link2HCH0002"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER II — BAKUNIN AND ANARCHISM </h2>
<p>IN the popular mind, an Anarchist is a person who throws bombs and commits
other outrages, either because he is more or less insane, or because he
uses the pretense of extreme political opinions as a cloak for criminal
proclivities. This view is, of course, in every way inadequate. Some
Anarchists believe in throwing bombs; many do not. Men of almost every
other shade of opinion believe in throwing bombs in suitable
circumstances: for example, the men who threw the bomb at Sarajevo which
started the present war were not Anarchists, but Nationalists. And those
Anarchists who are in favor of bomb-throwing do not in this respect differ
on any vital principle from the rest of the community, with the exception
of that infinitesimal portion who adopt the Tolstoyan attitude of
non-resistance. Anarchists, like Socialists, usually believe in the
doctrine of the class war, and if they use bombs, it is as Governments use
bombs, for purposes of war: but for every bomb manufactured by an
Anarchist, many millions are manufactured by Governments, and for every
man killed by Anarchist violence, many millions are killed by the violence
of States. We may, therefore, dismiss from our minds the whole question of
violence, which plays so large a part in the popular imagination, since it
is neither essential nor peculiar to those who adopt the Anarchist
position.</p>
<p>Anarchism, as its derivation indicates, is the theory which is opposed to
every kind of forcible government. It is opposed to the State as the
embodiment of the force employed in the government of the community. Such
government as Anarchism can tolerate must be free government, not merely
in the sense that it is that of a majority, but in the sense that it is
that assented to by all. Anarchists object to such institutions as the
police and the criminal law, by means of which the will of one part of the
community is forced upon another part. In their view, the democratic form
of government is not very enormously preferable to other forms so long as
minorities are compelled by force or its potentiality to submit to the
will of majorities. Liberty is the supreme good in the Anarchist creed,
and liberty is sought by the direct road of abolishing all forcible
control over the individual by the community.</p>
<p>Anarchism, in this sense, is no new doctrine. It is set forth admirably by
Chuang Tzu, a Chinese philosopher, who lived about the year 300 B. C.:—</p>
<p>Horses have hoofs to carry them over frost and snow; hair, to protect them
from wind and cold. They eat grass and drink water, and fling up their
heels over the champaign. Such is the real nature of horses. Palatial
dwellings are of no use to them.</p>
<p>One day Po Lo appeared, saying: "I understand the management of horses."</p>
<p>So he branded them, and clipped them, and pared their hoofs, and put
halters on them, tying them up by the head and shackling them by the feet,
and disposing them in stables, with the result that two or three in every
ten died. Then he kept them hungry and thirsty, trotting them and
galloping them, and grooming, and trimming, with the misery of the
tasselled bridle before and the fear of the knotted whip behind, until
more than half of them were dead.</p>
<p>The potter says: "I can do what I will with Clay. If I want it round, I
use compasses; if rectangular, a square."</p>
<p>The carpenter says: "I can do what I will with wood. If I want it curved,
I use an arc; if straight, a line."</p>
<p>But on what grounds can we think that the natures of clay and wood desire
this application of compasses and square, of arc and line? Nevertheless,
every age extols Po Lo for his skill in managing horses, and potters and
carpenters for their skill with clay and wood. Those who govern the empire
make the same mistake.</p>
<p>Now I regard government of the empire from quite a different point of
view.</p>
<p>The people have certain natural instincts:—to weave and clothe
themselves, to till and feed themselves. These are common to all humanity,
and all are agreed thereon. Such instincts are called "Heaven-sent."</p>
<p>And so in the days when natural instincts prevailed, men moved quietly and
gazed steadily. At that time there were no roads over mountains, nor
boats, nor bridges over water. All things were produced, each for its own
proper sphere. Birds and beasts multiplied, trees and shrubs grew up. The
former might be led by the hand; you could climb up and peep into the
raven's nest. For then man dwelt with birds and beasts, and all creation
was one. There were no distinctions of good and bad men. Being all equally
without knowledge, their virtue could not go astray. Being all equally
without evil desires, they were in a state of natural integrity, the
perfection of human existence.</p>
<p>But when Sages appeared, tripping up people over charity and fettering
them with duty to their neighbor, doubt found its way into the world. And
then, with their gushing over music and fussing over ceremony, the empire
became divided against itself.<SPAN href="#linknote-11" name="linknoteref-11" id="linknoteref-11"><small>11</small></SPAN></p>
<p>The modern Anarchism, in the sense in which we shall be concerned with it,
is associated with belief in the communal ownership of land and capital,
and is thus in an important respect akin to Socialism. This doctrine is
properly called Anarchist Com- munism, but as it embraces practically all
modern Anarchism, we may ignore individualist Anarchism altogether and
concentrate attention upon the communistic form. Socialism and Anarchist
Communism alike have arisen from the perception that private capital is a
source of tyranny by certain individuals over others. Orthodox Socialism
believes that the individual will become free if the State becomes the
sole capitalist. Anarchism, on the contrary, fears that in that case the
State might merely inherit the tyrannical propensities of the private
capitalist. Accordingly, it seeks for a means of reconciling communal
ownership with the utmost possible diminution in the powers of the State,
and indeed ultimately with the complete abolition of the State. It has
arisen mainly within the Socialist movement as its extreme left wing.</p>
<p>In the same sense in which Marx may be regarded as the founder of modern
Socialism, Bakunin may be regarded as the founder of Anarchist Communism.
But Bakunin did not produce, like Marx, a finished and systematic body of
doctrine. The nearest approach to this will be found in the writings of
his follower, Kropotkin. In order to explain modern Anarchism we shall
begin with the life of Bakunin<SPAN href="#linknote-12" name="linknoteref-12" id="linknoteref-12"><small>12</small></SPAN> and the history of his conflicts
with Marx, and shall then give a brief account of Anarchist theory as set
forth partly in his writings, but more in those of Kropotkin.<SPAN href="#linknote-13" name="linknoteref-13" id="linknoteref-13"><small>13</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Michel Bakunin was born in 1814 of a Russian aristocratic family. His
father was a diplomatist, who at the time of Bakunin's birth had retired
to his country estate in the Government of Tver. Bakunin entered the
school of artillery in Petersburg at the age of fifteen, and at the age of
eighteen was sent as an ensign to a regiment stationed in the Government
of Minsk. The Polish insurrection of 1880 had just been crushed. "The
spectacle of terrorized Poland," says Guillaume, "acted powerfully on the
heart of the young officer, and contributed to inspire in him the horror
of despotism." This led him to give up the military career after two
years' trial. In 1834 he resigned his commission and went to Moscow, where
he spent six years studying philosophy. Like all philosophical students of
that period, he became a Hegelian, and in 1840 he went to Berlin to
continue his studies, in the hope of ultimately becoming a professor. But
after this time his opinions underwent a rapid change. He found it
impossible to accept the Hegelian maxim that whatever is, is rational, and
in 1842 he migrated to Dresden, where he became associated with Arnold
Ruge, the publisher of "Deutsche Jahrbuecher." By this time he had become
a revolutionary, and in the following year he incurred the hostility of
the Saxon Government. This led him to go to Switzerland, where he came in
contact with a group of German Communists, but, as the Swiss police
importuned him and the Russian Government demanded his return, he removed
to Paris, where he remained from 1843 to 1847. These years in Paris were
important in the formation of his outlook and opinions. He became
acquainted with Proudhon, who exercised a considerable influence on him;
also with George Sand and many other well- known people. It was in Paris
that he first made the acquaintance of Marx and Engels, with whom he was
to carry on a lifelong battle. At a much later period, in 1871, he gave
the following account of his relations with Marx at this time:—</p>
<p>Marx was much more advanced than I was, as he remains to-day not more
advanced but incomparably more learned than I am. I knew then nothing of
political economy. I had not yet rid myself of metaphysical abstractions,
and my Socialism was only instinctive. He, though younger than I, was
already an atheist, an instructed materialist, a well-considered
Socialist. It was just at this time that he elaborated the first
foundations of his present system. We saw each other fairly often, for I
respected him much for his learning and his passionate and serious
devotion (always mixed, however, with personal vanity) to the cause of the
proletariat, and I sought eagerly his conversation, which was always
instructive and clever, when it was not inspired by a paltry hate, which,
alas! happened only too often. But there was never any frank intimacy
between as. Our temperaments would not suffer it. He called me a
sentimental idealist, and he was right; I called him a vain man,
perfidious and crafty, and I also was right.</p>
<p>Bakunin never succeeded in staying long in one place without incurring the
enmity of the authorities. In November, 1847, as the result of a speech
praising the Polish rising of 1830, he was expelled from France at the
request of the Russian Embassy, which, in order to rob him of public
sympathy, spread the unfounded report that he had been an agent of the
Russian Government, but was no longer wanted because he had gone too far.
The French Government, by calculated reticence, encouraged this story,
which clung to him more or less throughout his life.</p>
<p>Being compelled to leave France, he went to Brussels, where he renewed
acquaintance with Marx. A letter of his, written at this time, shows that
he entertained already that bitter hatred for which afterward he had so
much reason. "The Germans, artisans, Bornstedt, Marx and Engels—and,
above all, Marx—are here, doing their ordinary mischief. Vanity,
spite, gossip, theoretical overbearingness and practical pusillanimity—reflections
on life, action and simplicity, and complete absence of life, action and
simplicity—literary and argumentative artisans and repulsive
coquetry with them: `Feuerbach is a bourgeois,' and the word `bourgeois'
grown into an epithet and repeated ad nauseum, but all of them themselves
from head to foot, through and through, provincial bourgeois. With one
word, lying and stupidity, stupidity and lying. In this society there is
no possibility of drawing a free, full breath. I hold myself aloof from
them, and have declared quite decidedly that I will not join their
communistic union of artisans, and will have nothing to do with it."</p>
<p>The Revolution of 1848 led him to return to Paris and thence to Germany.
He had a quarrel with Marx over a matter in which he himself confessed
later that Marx was in the right. He became a member of the Slav Congress
in Prague, where he vainly endeavored to promote a Slav insurrection.
Toward the end of 1848, he wrote an "Appeal to Slavs," calling on them to
combine with other revolutionaries to destroy the three oppressive
monarchies, Russia, Austria and Prussia. Marx attacked him in print,
saying, in effect, that the movement for Bohemian independence was futile
because the Slavs had no future, at any rate in those regions where they
hap- pened to be subject to Germany and Austria. Bakunin accused Mars of
German patriotism in this matter, and Marx accused him of Pan-Slavism, no
doubt in both cases justly. Before this dispute, however, a much more
serious quarrel had taken place. Marx's paper, the "Neue Rheinische
Zeitung," stated that George Sand had papers proving Bakunin to be a
Russian Government agent and one of those responsible for the recent
arrest of Poles. Bakunin, of course, repudiated the charge, and George
Sand wrote to the "Neue Rheinische Zeitung," denying this statement in
toto. The denials were published by Marx, and there was a nominal
reconciliation, but from this time onward there was never any real
abatement of the hostility between these rival leaders, who did not meet
again until 1864.</p>
<p>Meanwhile, the reaction had been everywhere gaining ground. In May, 1849,
an insurrection in Dresden for a moment made the revolutionaries masters
of the town. They held it for five days and established a revolutionary
government. Bakunin was the soul of the defense which they made against
the Prussian troops. But they were overpowered, and at last Bakunin was
captured while trying to escape with Heubner and Richard Wagner, the last
of whom, fortunately for music, was not captured.</p>
<p>Now began a long period of imprisonment in many prisons and various
countries. Bakunin was sentenced to death on the 14th of January, 1850,
but his sentence was commuted after five months, and he was delivered over
to Austria, which claimed the privilege of punishing him. The Austrians,
in their turn, condemned him to death in May, 1851, and again his sentence
was commuted to imprisonment for life. In the Austrian prisons he had
fetters on hands and feet, and in one of them he was even chained to the
wall by the belt. There seems to have been some peculiar pleasure to be
derived from the punishment of Bakunin, for the Russian Government in its
turn demanded him of the Austrians, who delivered him up. In Russia he was
confined, first in the Peter and Paul fortress and then in the
Schluesselburg. There be suffered from scurvy and all his teeth fell out.
His health gave way completely, and he found almost all food impossible to
assimilate. "But, if his body became enfeebled, his spirit remained
inflexible. He feared one thing above all. It was to find himself some day
led, by the debilitating action of prison, to the condition of degradation
of which Silvio Pellico offers a well-known type. He feared that he might
cease to hate, that he might feel the sentiment of revolt which upheld him
becoming extinguished in his hearts that he might come to pardon his
persecutors and resign himself to his fate. But this fear was superfluous;
his energy did not abandon him a single day, and he emerged from his cell
the same man as when he entered."<SPAN href="#linknote-14"
name="linknoteref-14" id="linknoteref-14"><small>14</small></SPAN></p>
<p>After the death of the Tsar Nicholas many political prisoners were
amnested, but Alexander II with his own hand erased Bakunin's name from
the list. When Bakunin's mother succeeded in obtaining an interview with
the new Tsar, he said to her, "Know, Madame, that so long as your son
lives, he can never be free." However, in 1857, after eight years of
captivity, he was sent to the comparative freedom of Siberia. From there,
in 1861, he succeeded in escaping to Japan, and thence through America to
London. He had been imprisoned for his hostility to governments, but,
strange to say, his sufferings had not had the intended effect of making
him love those who inflicted them. From this time onward, he devoted
himself to spreading the spirit of Anarchist revolt, without, however,
having to suffer any further term of imprisonment. For some years he lived
in Italy, where he founded in 1864 an "International Fraternity" or
"Alliance of Socialist Revolutionaries." This contained men of many
countries, but apparently no Germans. It devoted itself largely to
combating Mazzini's nationalism. In 1867 he moved to Switzerland, where in
the following year he helped to found the "International Alliance of So-
cialist Democracy," of which he drew up the program. This program gives a
good succinct resume of his opinions:—</p>
<p>The Alliance declares itself atheist; it desires the definitive and entire
abolition of classes and the political equality and social equalization of
individuals of both sexes. It desires that the earth, the instrument of
labor, like all other capital, becoming the collective property of society
as a whole, shall be no longer able to be utilized except by the workers,
that is to say, by agricultural and industrial associations. It recognizes
that all actually existing political and authoritarian States, reducing
themselves more and more to the mere administrative functions of the
public services in their respective countries, must disappear in the
universal union of free associations, both agricultural and industrial.</p>
<p>The International Alliance of Socialist Democracy desired to become a
branch of the International Working Men's Association, but was refused
admission on the ground that branches must be local, and could not
themselves be international. The Geneva group of the Alliance, however,
was admitted later, in July, 1869.</p>
<p>The International Working Men's Association had been founded in London in
1864, and its statutes and program were drawn up by Marx. Bakunin at first
did not expect it to prove a success and refused to join it. But it spread
with remarkable rapidity in many countries and soon became a great power
for the propagation of Socialist ideas. Originally it was by no means
wholly Socialist, but in successive Congresses Marx won it over more and
more to his views. At its third Congress, in Brussels in September, 1868,
it became definitely Socialist. Meanwhile Bakunin, regretting his earlier
abstention, had decided to join it, and he brought with him a considerable
following in French-Switzerland, France, Spain and Italy. At the fourth
Congress, held at Basle in September, 1869, two currents were strongly
marked. The Germans and English followed Marx in his belief in the State
as it was to become after the abolition of private property; they followed
him also in his desire to found Labor Parties in the various countries,
and to utilize the machinery of democracy for the election of
representatives of Labor to Parliaments. On the other hand, the Latin
nations in the main followed Bakunin in opposing the State and
disbelieving in the machinery of representative government. The conflict
between these two groups grew more and more bitter, and each accused the
other of various offenses. The statement that Bakunin was a spy was
repeated, but was withdrawn after investigation. Marx wrote in a
confidential communication to his German friends that Bakunin was an agent
of the Pan-Slavist party and received from them 25,000 francs a year.
Meanwhile, Bakunin became for a time interested in the attempt to stir up
an agrarian revolt in Russia, and this led him to neglect the contest in
the International at a crucial moment. During the Franco-Prussian war
Bakunin passionately took the side of France, especially after the fall of
Napoleon III. He endeavored to rouse the people to revolutionary
resistance like that of 1793, and became involved in an abortive attempt
at revolt in Lyons. The French Government accused him of being a paid
agent of Prussia, and it was with difficulty that he escaped to
Switzerland. The dispute with Marx and his followers had become
exacerbated by the national dispute. Bakunin, like Kropotkin after him,
regarded the new power of Germany as the greatest menace to liberty in the
world. He hated the Germans with a bitter hatred, partly, no doubt, on
account of Bismarck, but probably still more on account of Marx. To this
day, Anarchism has remained confined almost exclusively to the Latin
countries, and has been associated with, a hatred of Germany, growing out
of the contests between Marx and Bakunin in the International.</p>
<p>The final suppression of Bakunin's faction occurred at the General
Congress of the International at the Hague in 1872. The meeting-place was
chosen by the General Council (in which Marx was unopposed), with a view—so
Bakunin's friends contend— to making access impossible for Bakunin
(on account of the hostility of the French and German governments) and
difficult for his friends. Bakunin was expelled from the International as
the result of a report accusing him inter alia of theft backed; up by
intimidation.</p>
<p>The orthodoxy of the International was saved, but at the cost of its
vitality. From this time onward, it ceased to be itself a power, but both
sections continued to work in their various groups, and the Socialist
groups in particular grew rapidly. Ultimately a new International was
formed (1889) which continued down to the outbreak of the present war. As
to the future of International Socialism it would be rash to prophesy,
though it would seem that the international idea has acquired sufficient
strength to need again, after the war, some such means of expression as it
found before in Socialist congresses.</p>
<p>By this time Bakunin's health was broken, and except for a few brief
intervals, he lived in retirement until his death in 1876.</p>
<p>Bakunin's life, unlike Marx's, was a very stormy one. Every kind of
rebellion against authority always aroused his sympathy, and in his
support he never paid the slightest attention to personal risk. His
influence, undoubtedly very great, arose chiefly through the influence of
his personality upon important individuals. His writings differ from
Marx's as much as his life does, and in a similar way. They are chaotic,
largely, aroused by some passing occasion, abstract and metaphysical,
except when they deal with current politics. He does not come to close
quarters with economic facts, but dwells usually in the regions of theory
and metaphysics. When he descends from these regions, he is much more at
the mercy of current international politics than Marx, much less imbued
with the consequences of the belief that it is economic causes that are
fundamental. He praised Marx for enunciating this doctrine,<SPAN href="#linknote-15" name="linknoteref-15" id="linknoteref-15"><small>15</small></SPAN>
but nevertheless continued to think in terms of nations. His longest work,
"L'Empire Knouto-Germanique et la Revolution Sociale," is mainly concerned
with the situation in France during the later stages of the
Franco-Prussian War, and with the means of resisting German imperialism.
Most of his writing was done in a hurry in the interval between two
insurrections. There is something of Anarchism in his lack of literary
order. His best-known work is a fragment entitled by its editors "God and
the State."<SPAN href="#linknote-16" name="linknoteref-16" id="linknoteref-16"><small>16</small></SPAN></p>
<p>In this work he represents belief in God and belief in the State as the
two great obstacles to human liberty. A typical passage will serve to
illustrate its style.</p>
<p>The State is not society, it is only an historical form of it, as brutal
as it is abstract. It was born historically in all countries of the
marriage of violence, rapine, pillage, in a word, war and conquest, with
the gods successively created by the theological fantasy of nations. It
has been from its origin, and it remains still at present, the divine
sanction of brutal force and triumphant inequality.</p>
<p>The State is authority; it is force; it is the ostentation and infatuation
of force: it does not insinuate itself; it does not seek to convert. . . .
Even when it commands what is good, it hinders and spoils it, just because
it commands it, and because every command provokes and excites the
legitimate revolts of liberty; and because the good, from the moment that
it is commanded, becomes evil from the point of view of true morality, of
human morality (doubtless not of divine), from the point of view of human
respect and of liberty. Liberty, morality, and the human dignity of man
consist precisely in this, that he does good, not because it is commanded,
but because he conceives it, wills it and loves it.</p>
<p>We do not find in Bakunin's works a clear picture of the society at which
he aimed, or any argument to prove that such a society could be stable. If
we wish to understand Anarchism we must turn to his followers, and
especially to Kropotkin—like him, a Russian aristocrat familiar with
the prisons of Europe, and, like him, an Anarchist who, in spite of his
internationalism, is imbued with a fiery hatred of the Germans.</p>
<p>Kropotkin has devoted much of his writing to technical questions of
production. In "Fields, Factories and Workshops" and "The Conquest of
Bread" he has set himself to prove that, if production were more
scientific and better organized, a comparatively small amount of quite
agreeable work would suffice to keep the whole population in comfort. Even
assuming, as we probably must, that he somewhat exaggerates what is
possible with our present scientific knowledge, it must nevertheless be
conceded that his contentions contain a very large measure of truth. In
attacking the subject of production he has shown that he knows what is the
really crucial question. If civilization and progress are to be compatible
with equality, it is necessary that equality should not involve long hours
of painful toil for little more than the necessaries of life, since, where
there is no leisure, art and science will die and all progress will become
impossible. The objection which some feel to Socialism and Anarchism alike
on this ground cannot be upheld in view of the possible productivity of
labor.</p>
<p>The system at which Kropotkin aims, whether or not it be possible, is
certainly one which demands a very great improvement in the methods of
production above what is common at present. He desires to abolish wholly
the system of wages, not only, as most Socialists do, in the sense that a
man is to be paid rather for his willingness to work than for the actual
work demanded of him, but in a more fundamental sense: there is to be no
obligation to work, and all things are to be shared in equal proportions
among the whole population. Kropotkin relies upon the possibility of
making work pleasant: he holds that, in such a community as he foresees,
practically everyone will prefer work to idleness, because work will not
involve overwork or slavery, or that excessive specialization that
industrialism has brought about, but will be merely a pleasant activity
for certain hours of the day, giving a man an outlet for his spontaneous
constructive impulses. There is to be no compulsion, no law, no government
exercising force; there will still be acts of the community, but these are
to spring from universal consent, not from any enforced submission of even
the smallest minority. We shall examine in a later chapter how far such an
ideal is realizable, but it cannot be denied that Kropotkin presents it
with extraordinary persuasiveness and charm.</p>
<p>We should be doing more than justice to Anarchism if we did not say
something of its darker side, the side which has brought it into conflict
with the police and made it a word of terror to ordinary citizens. In its
general doctrines there is nothing essentially involving violent methods
or a virulent hatred of the rich, and many who adopt these general
doctrines are personally gentle and temperamentally averse from violence.
But the general tone of the Anarchist press and public is bitter to a
degree that seems scarcely sane, and the appeal, especially in Latin
countries, is rather to envy of the fortunate than to pity for the
unfortunate. A vivid and readable, though not wholly reliable, account,
from a hostile point of view, is given in a book called "Le Peril
Anarchiste," by Felix Dubois,<SPAN href="#linknote-17" name="linknoteref-17" id="linknoteref-17"><small>17</small></SPAN> which incidentally reproduces a
number of cartoons from anarchist journals. The revolt against law
naturally leads, except in those who are controlled by a real passion for
humanity, to a relaxation of all the usually accepted moral rules, and to
a bitter spirit of retaliatory cruelty out of which good can hardly come.</p>
<p>One of the most curious features of popular Anarchism is its martyrology,
aping Christian forms, with the guillotine (in France) in place of the
cross. Many who have suffered death at the hands of the authorities on
account of acts of violence were no doubt genuine sufferers for their
belief in a cause, but others, equally honored, are more questionable. One
of the most curious examples of this outlet for the repressed religious
impulse is the cult of Ravachol, who was guillotined in 1892 on account of
various dynamite outrages. His past was dubious, but he died defiantly;
his last words were three lines from a well-known Anarchist song, the
"Chant du Pere Duchesne":—</p>
<p>Si tu veux etre heureux,<br/>
Nom de Dieu!<br/>
Pends ton proprietaire.<br/></p>
<p>As was natural, the leading Anarchists took no part in the canonization of
his memory; nevertheless it proceeded, with the most amazing
extravagances.</p>
<p>It would be wholly unfair to judge Anarchist doctrine, or the views of its
leading exponents, by such phenomena; but it remains a fact that Anarchism
attracts to itself much that lies on the borderland of insanity and common
crime.<SPAN href="#linknote-18" name="linknoteref-18" id="linknoteref-18"><small>18</small></SPAN>
This must be remembered in exculpation of the authorities and the
thoughtless public, who often confound in a common detestation the
parasites of the movement and the truly heroic and high-minded men who
have elaborated its theories and sacrificed comfort and success to their
propagation.</p>
<p>The terrorist campaign in which such men as Ravachol were active
practically came to an end in 1894. After that time, under the influence
of Pelloutier, the better sort of Anarchists found a less harmful outlet
by advocating Revolutionary Syndicalism in the Trade Unions and Bourses du
Travail.<SPAN href="#linknote-19" name="linknoteref-19" id="linknoteref-19"><small>19</small></SPAN></p>
<p>The ECONOMIC organization of society, as conceived by Anarchist
Communists, does not differ greatly from that which is sought by
Socialists. Their difference from Socialists is in the matter of
government: they demand that government shall require the consent of all
the governed, and not only of a majority. It is undeniable that the rule
of a majority may be almost as hostile to freedom as the rule of a
minority: the divine right of majorities is a dogma as little possessed of
absolute truth as any other. A strong democratic State may easily be led
into oppression of its best citizens, namely, those those independence of
mind would make them a force for progress. Experience of democratic
parliamentary government has shown that it falls very far short of what
was expected of it by early Socialists, and the Anarchist revolt against
it is not surprising. But in the form of pure Anarchism, this revolt has
remained weak and sporadic. It is Syndicalism, and the movements to which
Syndicalism has given rise, that have popularized the revolt against
parliamentary government and purely political means of emancipating the
wage earner. But this movement must be dealt with in a separate chapter.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0003" id="link2HCH0003"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER III — THE SYNDICALIST REVOLT </h2>
<p>SYNDICALISM arose in France as a revolt against political Socialism, and
in order to understand it we must trace in brief outline the positions
attained by Socialist parties in the various countries.</p>
<p>After a severe setback, caused by the Franco- Prussian war, Socialism
gradually revived, and in all the countries of Western Europe Socialist
parties have increased their numerical strength almost continuously during
the last forty years; but, as is invariably the case with a growing sect,
the intensity of faith has diminished as the number of believers has
increased.</p>
<p>In Germany the Socialist party became the strongest faction of the
Reichstag, and, in spite of differences of opinion among its members, it
preserved its formal unity with that instinct for military discipline
which characterizes the German nation. In the Reichstag election of 1912
it polled a third of the total number of votes cast, and returned 110
members out of a total of 397. After the death of Bebel, the Revisionists,
who received their first impulse from Bernstein, overcame the more strict
Marxians, and the party became in effect merely one of advanced
Radicalism. It is too soon to guess what will be the effect of the split
between Majority and Minority Socialists which has occurred during the
war. There is in Germany hardly a trace of Syndicalism; its characteristic
doctrine, the preference of industrial to political action, has found
scarcely any support.</p>
<p>In England Marx has never had many followers. Socialism there has been
inspired in the main by the Fabians (founded in 1883), who threw over the
advocacy of revolution, the Marxian doctrine of value, and the class-war.
What remained was State Socialism and a doctrine of "permeation." Civil
servants were to be permeated with the realization that Socialism would
enormously increase their power. Trade Unions were to be permeated with
the belief that the day for purely industrial action was past, and that
they must look to government (inspired secretly by sympathetic civil
servants) to bring about, bit by bit, such parts of the Socialist program
as were not likely to rouse much hostility in the rich. The Independent
Labor Party (formed in 1893) was largely inspired at first by the ideas of
the Fabians, though retaining to the present day, and especially since the
outbreak of the war, much more of the original Socialist ardor. It aimed
always at co-operation with the industrial organizations of wage-earners,
and, chiefly through its efforts, the Labor Party<SPAN href="#linknote-20"
name="linknoteref-20" id="linknoteref-20"><small>20</small></SPAN> was formed
in 1900 out of a combination of the Trade Unions and the political
Socialists. To this party, since 1909, all the important Unions have
belonged, but in spite of the fact that its strength is derived from Trade
Unions, it has stood always for political rather than industrial action.
Its Socialism has been of a theoretical and academic order, and in
practice, until the outbreak of war, the Labor members in Parliament (of
whom 30 were elected in 1906 and 42 in December, 1910) might be reckoned
almost as a part of the Liberal Party.</p>
<p>France, unlike England and Germany, was not content merely to repeat the
old shibboleths with continually diminishing conviction. In France<SPAN href="#linknote-21" name="linknoteref-21" id="linknoteref-21"><small>21</small></SPAN>
a new movement, originally known as Revolutionary Syndicalism—and
afterward simply as Syndicalism— kept alive the vigor of the
original impulse, and remained true to the spirit of the older Socialists,
while departing from the letter. Syndicalism, unlike Socialism and
Anarchism, began from an existing organization and developed the ideas
appropriate to it, whereas Socialism and Anarchism began with the ideas
and only afterward developed the organizations which were their vehicle.
In order to understand Syndicalism, we have first to describe Trade Union
organization in France, and its political environment. The ideas of
Syndicalism will then appear as the natural outcome of the political and
economic situation. Hardly any of these ideas are new; almost all are
derived from the Bakunist section of the old International.
The old International had considerable success in France before the
Franco- Prussian War; indeed, in 1869, it is estimated to have had a
French membership of a quarter of a million. What is practically the
Syndicalist program was advocated by a French delegate to the Congress of
the International at Bale in that same year.<SPAN href="#linknote-22"
name="linknoteref-22" id="linknoteref-22"><small>22</small></SPAN></p>
<p>The war of 1870 put an end for the time being to the Socialist Movement in
France. Its revival was begun by Jules Guesde in 1877. Unlike the Ger- man
Socialists, the French have been split into many different factions. In
the early eighties there was a split between the Parliamentary Socialists
and the Communist Anarchists. The latter thought that the first act of the
Social Revolution should be the destruction of the State, and would
therefore have nothing to do with Parliamentary politics. The Anarchists,
from 1883 onward, had success in Paris and the South. The Socialists
contended that the State will disappear after the Socialist society has
been firmly established. In 1882 the Socialists split between the
followers of Guesde, who claimed to represent the revolutionary and
scientific Socialism of Marx, and the followers of Paul Brousse, who were
more opportunist and were also called possibilists and cared little for
the theories of Marx. In 1890 there was a secession from the Broussists,
who followed Allemane and absorbed the more revolutionary elements of the
party and became leading spirits in some of the strongest syndicates.
Another group was the Independent Socialists, among whom were Jaures,
Millerand and Viviani.<SPAN href="#linknote-23" name="linknoteref-23" id="linknoteref-23"><small>23</small></SPAN></p>
<p>The disputes between the various sections of Socialists caused
difficulties in the Trade Unions and helped to bring about the resolution
to keep politics out of the Unions. From this to Syndicalism was an easy
step.</p>
<p>Since the year 1905, as the result of a union between the Parti Socialiste
de France (Part; Ouvrier Socialiste Revolutionnaire Francais led by
Guesde) and the Parti Socialiste Francais (Jaures), there have been only
two groups of Socialists, the United Socialist Party and the Independents,
who are intellectuals or not willing to be tied to a party. At the General
Election of 1914 the former secured 102 members and the latter 30, out of
a total of 590.</p>
<p>Tendencies toward a rapprochement between the various groups were
seriously interfered with by an event which had considerable importance
for the whole development of advanced political ideas in France, namely,
the acceptance of office in the Waldeck- Rousseau Ministry by the
Socialist Millerand in 1899. Millerand, as was to be expected, soon ceased
to be a Socialist, and the opponents of political action pointed to his
development as showing the vanity of political triumphs. Very many French
politicians who have risen to power have begun their political career as
Socialists, and have ended it not infrequently by employing the army to
oppress strikers. Millerand's action was the most notable and dramatic
among a number of others of a similar kind. Their cumulative effect has
been to produce a certain cynicism in regard to politics among the more
class-conscious of French wage-earners, and this state of mind greatly
assisted the spread of Syndicalism.</p>
<p>Syndicalism stands essentially for the point of view of the producer as
opposed to that of the consumer; it is concerned with reforming actual
work, and the organization of industry, not MERELY with securing greater
rewards for work. From this point of view its vigor and its distinctive
character are derived. It aims at substituting industrial for political
action, and at using Trade Union organization for purposes for which
orthodox Socialism would look to Parliament. "Syndicalism" was originally
only the French name for Trade Unionism, but the Trade Unionists of France
became divided into two sections, the Reformist and the Revolutionary, of
whom the latter only professed the ideas which we now associate with the
term "Syndicalism." It is quite impossible to guess how far either the
organization or the ideas of the Syndicalists will remain intact at the
end of the war, and everything that we shall say is to be taken as
applying only to the years before the war. It may be that French
Syndicalism as a distinctive movement will be dead, but even in that case
it will not have lost its importance, since it has given a new impulse and
direction to the more vigorous part of the labor movement in all civilized
countries, with the possible exception of Germany.</p>
<p>The organization upon which Syndicalism de- pended was the Confederation
Generale du Travail, commonly known as the C. G. T., which was founded in
1895, but only achieved its final form in 1902. It has never been
numerically very powerful, but has derived its influence from the fact
that in moments of crisis many who were not members were willing to follow
its guidance. Its membership in the year before the war is estimated by
Mr. Cole at somewhat more than half a million. Trade Unions (Syndicats)
were legalized by Waldeck-Rousseau in 1884, and the C. G. T., on its
inauguration in 1895, was formed by the Federation of 700 Syndicats.
Alongside of this organization there existed another, the Federation des
Bourses du Travail, formed in 1893. A Bourse du Travail is a local
organization, not of any one trade, but of local labor in general,
intended to serve as a Labor Exchange and to perform such functions for
labor as Chambers of Commerce perform for the employer.<SPAN href="#linknote-24" name="linknoteref-24" id="linknoteref-24"><small>24</small></SPAN>
A Syndicat is in general a local organization of a single industry, and is
thus a smaller unit than the Bourse du Travail.<SPAN href="#linknote-25"
name="linknoteref-25" id="linknoteref-25"><small>25</small></SPAN> Under the
able leadership of Pelloutier, the Federation des Bourses prospered more
than the C. G. T., and at last, in 1902, coalesced with it. The result was
an organization in which the local Syndicat was fed- erated twice over,
once with the other Syndicat in its locality, forming together the local
Bourse du Travail, and again with the Syndicats in the same industry in
other places. "It was the purpose of the new organization to secure twice
over the membership of every syndicat, to get it to join both its local
Bourse du Travail and the Federation of its industry. The Statutes of the
C. G. T. (I. 3) put this point plainly: `No Syndicat will be able to form
a part of the C. G. T. if it is not federated nationally and an adherent
of a Bourse du Travail or a local or departmental Union of Syndicats
grouping different associations.' Thus, M. Lagardelle explains, the two
sections will correct each other's point of view: national federation of
industries will prevent parochialism (localisme), and local organization
will check the corporate or `Trade Union' spirit. The workers will learn
at once the solidarity of all workers in a locality and that of all
workers in a trade, and, in learning this, they will learn at the same
time the complete solidarity of the whole working-class."<SPAN href="#linknote-26" name="linknoteref-26" id="linknoteref-26"><small>26</small></SPAN></p>
<p>This organization was largely the work of Pellouties, who was Secretary of
the Federation des Bourses from 1894 until his death in 1901. He was an
Anarchist Communist and impressed his ideas upon the Federation and thence
posthumously on the C. G. T. after its combination with the Federation des
Bourses. He even carried his principles into the government of the
Federation; the Committee had no chairman and votes very rarely took
place. He stated that "the task of the revolution is to free mankind, not
only from all authority, but also from every institution which has not for
its essential purpose the development of production."</p>
<p>The C. G. T. allows much autonomy to each unit in the organization. Each
Syndicat counts for one, whether it be large or small. There are not the
friendly society activities which form so large a part of the work of
English Unions. It gives no orders, but is purely advisory. It does not
allow politics to be introduced into the Unions. This decision was
originally based upon the fact that the divisions among Socialists
disrupted the Unions, but it is now reinforced in the minds of an
important section by the general Anarchist dislike of politics. The C. G.
T. is essentially a fighting organization; in strikes, it is the nucleus
to which the other workers rally.</p>
<p>There is a Reformist section in the C. G. T., but it is practically always
in a minority, and the C. G. T. is, to all intents and purposes, the organ
of revolutionary Syndicalism, which is simply the creed of its leaders.</p>
<p>The essential doctrine of Syndicalism is the class- war, to be conducted
by industrial rather than politi- cal methods. The chief industrial
methods advocated are the strike, the boycott, the label and sabotage.</p>
<p>The boycott, in various forms, and the label, showing that the work has
been done under trade- union conditions, have played a considerable part
in American labor struggles.</p>
<p>Sabotage is the practice of doing bad work, or spoiling machinery or work
which has already been done, as a method of dealing with employers in a
dispute when a strike appears for some reason undesirable or impossible.
It has many forms, some clearly innocent, some open to grave objections.
One form of sabotage which has been adopted by shop assistants is to tell
customers the truth about the articles they are buying; this form, however
it may damage the shopkeeper's business, is not easy to object to on moral
grounds. A form which has been adopted on railways, particularly in
Italian strikes, is that of obeying all rules literally and exactly, in
such a way as to make the running of trains practically impossible.
Another form is to do all the work with minute care, so that in the end it
is better done, but the output is small. From these innocent forms there
is a continual progression, until we come to such acts as all ordinary
morality would consider criminal; for example, causing railway accidents.
Advocates of sabotage justify it as part of war, but in its more violent
forms (in which it is seldom defended) it is cruel and probably
inexpedient, while even in its milder forms it must tend to encourage
slovenly habits of work, which might easily persist under the new regime
that the Syndicalists wish to introduce. At the same time, when
capitalists express a moral horror of this method, it is worth while to
observe that they themselves are the first to practice it when the
occasion seems to them appropriate. If report speaks truly, an example of
this on a very large scale has been seen during the Russian Revolution.</p>
<p>By far the most important of the Syndicalist methods is the strike.
Ordinary strikes, for specific objects, are regarded as rehearsals, as a
means of perfecting organization and promoting enthusiasm, but even when
they are victorious so far as concerns the specific point in dispute, they
are not regarded by Syndicalists as affording any ground for industrial
peace. Syndicalists aim at using the strike, not to secure such
improvements of detail as employers may grant, but to destroy the whole
system of employer and employed and win the complete emancipation of the
worker. For this purpose what is wanted is the General Strike, the
complete cessation of work by a sufficient proportion of the wage-earners
to secure the paralysis of capitalism. Sorel, who represents Syndicalism
too much in the minds of the reading public, suggests that the General
Strike is to be regarded as a myth, like the Second Coming in Christian
doctrine. But this view by no means suits the active Syndicalists. If they
were brought to believe that the General Strike is a mere myth, their
energy would flag, and their whole outlook would become disillusioned. It
is the actual, vivid belief in its possibility which inspires them. They
are much criticised for this belief by the political Socialists who
consider that the battle is to be won by obtaining a Parliamentary
majority. But Syndicalists have too little faith in the honesty of
politicians to place any reliance on such a method or to believe in the
value of any revolution which leaves the power of the State intact.</p>
<p>Syndicalist aims are somewhat less definite than Syndicalist methods. The
intellectuals who endeavor to interpret them—not always very
faithfully— represent them as a party of movement and change,
following a Bergsonian elan vital, without needing any very clear
prevision of the goal to which it is to take them. Nevertheless, the
negative part, at any rate, of their objects is sufficiently clear.</p>
<p>They wish to destroy the State, which they regard as a capitalist
institution, designed essentially to terrorize the workers. They refuse to
believe that it would be any better under State Socialism. They desire to
see each industry self-governing, but as to the means of adjusting the
relations between different industries, they are not very clear. They are
anti-militarist because they are anti-State, and because French troops
have often been employed against them in strikes; also because they are
internationalists, who believe that the sole interest of the working man
everywhere is to free himself from the tyranny of the capitalist. Their
outlook on life is the very reverse of pacifist, but they oppose wars
between States on the ground that these are not fought for objects that in
any way concern the workers. Their anti-militarism, more than anything
else, brought them into conflict with the authorities in the years
preceding the war. But, as was to be expected, it did not survive the
actual invasion of France.</p>
<p>The doctrines of Syndicalism may be illustrated by an article introducing
it to English readers in the first number of "The Syndicalist Railwayman,"
September, 1911, from which the following is quoted:—</p>
<p>"All Syndicalism, Collectivism, Anarchism aims at abolishing the present
economic status and existing private ownership of most things; but while
Collectivism would substitute ownership by everybody, and Anarchism
ownership by nobody, Syndicalism aims at ownership by Organized Labor. It
is thus a purely Trade Union reading of the economic doctrine and the
class war preached by Socialism. It vehemently repudiates Parliamentary
action on which Collectivism relies; and it is, in this respect, much more
closely allied to Anarchism, from which, indeed, it differs in practice
only in being more limited in range of action." (Times, Aug. 25, 1911).</p>
<p>In truth, so thin is the partition between Syndicalism and Anarchism that
the newer and less familiar "ism" has been shrewdly defined as "Organized
Anarchy." It has been created by the Trade Unions of France; but it is
obviously an international plant, whose roots have already found the soil
of Britain most congenial to its growth and fructification.</p>
<p>Collectivist or Marxian Socialism would have us believe that it is
distinctly a LABOR Movement; but it is not so. Neither is Anarchism. The
one is substantially bourgeois; the other aristocratic, plus an abundant
output of book-learning, in either case. Syndicalism, on the contrary, is
indubitably laborist in origin and aim, owing next to nothing to the
"Classes," and, indeed,, resolute to uproot them. The Times (Oct. 13,
1910), which almost single-handed in the British Press has kept creditably
abreast of Continental Syndicalism, thus clearly set forth the
significance of the General Strike:</p>
<p>"To understand what it means, we must remember that there is in France a
powerful Labor Organization which has for its open and avowed object a
Revolution, in which not only the present order of Society, but the State
itself, is to be swept away. This movement is called Syndicalism. It is
not Socialism, but, on the contrary, radically opposed to Socialism,
because the Syndicalists hold that the State is the great enemy and that
the Socialists' ideal of State or Collectivist Ownership would make the
lot of the Workers much worse than it is now under private employers. The
means by which they hope to attain their end is the General Strike, an
idea which was invented by a French workman about twenty years ago,<SPAN href="#linknote-27" name="linknoteref-27" id="linknoteref-27"><small>27</small></SPAN>
and was adopted by the French Labor Congress in 1894, after a furious
battle with the Socialists, in which the latter were worsted. Since then
the General Strike has been the avowed policy of the Syndicalists, whose
organization is the Confederation Generale du Travail."</p>
<p>Or, to put it otherwise, the intelligent French worker has awakened, as he
believes, to the fact that Society (Societas) and the State (Civitas)
connote two separable spheres of human activity, between which there is no
connection, necessary or desirable. Without the one, man, being a
gregarious animal, cannot subsist: while without the other he would simply
be in clover. The "statesman" whom office does not render positively
nefarious is at best an expensive superfluity.</p>
<p>Syndicalists have had many violent encounters with the forces of
government. In 1907 and 1908, protesting against bloodshed which had
occurred in the suppression of strikes, the Committee of the C. G. T.
issued manifestoes speaking of the Government as "a Government of
assassins" and alluding to the Prime Minister as "Clemenceau the
murderer." Similar events in the strike at Villeneuve St. Georges in 1908
led to the arrest of all the leading members of the Committee. In the
railway strike of October, 1910, Monsieur Briand arrested the Strike
Committee, mobilized the railway men and sent soldiers to replace
strikers. As a result of these vigorous measures the strike was completely
defeated, and after this the chief energy of the C. G. T. was directed
against militarism and nationalism.</p>
<p>The attitude of Anarchism to the Syndicalist movement is sympathetic, with
the reservation that such methods as the General Strike are not to be
regarded as substitutes for the violent revolution which most Anarchists
consider necessary. Their attitude in this matter was defined at the
International Anarchist Congress held in Amsterdam in August, 1907. This
Congress recommended "comrades of all countries to actively participate in
autonomous movements of the working class, and to develop in Syndicalist
organizations the ideas of revolt, individual initiative and solidarity,
which are the essence of Anarchism." Comrades were to "propagate and
support only those forms and manifestations of direct action which carry,
in themselves, a revolutionary character and lead to the transformation of
society." It was resolved that "the Anarchists think that the destruction
of the capitalist and authoritary society can only be realized by armed
insurrection and violent expropriation, and that the use of the more or
less General Strike and the Syndicalist movement must not make us forget
the more direct means of struggle against the military force of
government."</p>
<p>Syndicalists might retort that when the movement is strong enough to win
by armed insurrection it will be abundantly strong enough to win by the
General Strike. In Labor movements generally, success through violence can
hardly be expected except in circumstances where success without violence
is attainable. This argument alone, even if there were no other, would be
a very powerful reason against the methods advocated by the Anarchist
Congress.</p>
<p>Syndicalism stands for what is known as industrial unionism as opposed to
craft unionism. In this respect, as also in the preference of industrial
to political methods, it is part of a movement which has spread far beyond
France. The distinction between industrial and craft unionism is much
dwelt on by Mr. Cole. Craft unionism "unites in a single association those
workers who are engaged on a single industrial process, or on processes so
nearly akin that any one can do another's work." But "organization may
follow the lines, not of the work done, but of the actual structure of
industry. All workers working at producing a particular kind of commodity
may be organized in a single Union. . . . The basis of organization would
be neither the craft to which a man belonged nor the employer under whom
he worked, but the service on which he was engaged. This is Industrial
Unionism properly so called.<SPAN href="#linknote-28" name="linknoteref-28" id="linknoteref-28"><small>28</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Industrial unionism is a product of America, and from America it has to
some extent spread to Great Britain. It is the natural form of fighting
organization when the union is regarded as the means of carrying on the
class war with a view, not to obtaining this or that minor amelioration,
but to a radical revolution in the economic system. This is the point of
view adopted by the "Industrial Workers of the World," commonly known as
the I. W. W. This organization more or less corresponds in America to what
the C. G. T. was in France before the war. The differences between the two
are those due to the different economic circumstances of the two
countries, but their spirit is closely analogous. The I. W. W. is not
united as to the ultimate form which it wishes society to take. There are
Socialists, Anarchists and Syndicalists among its members. But it is clear
on the immediate practical issue, that the class war is the fundamental
reality in the present relations of labor and capital, and that it is by
industrial action, especially by the strike, that emancipation must be
sought. The I. W. W., like the C. G. T., is not nearly so strong
numerically as it is supposed to be by those who fear it. Its influence is
based, not upon its numbers, but upon its power of enlisting the
sympathies of the workers in moments of crisis.</p>
<p>The labor movement in America has been characterized on both sides by very
great violence. Indeed, the Secretary of the C. G. T., Monsieur Jouhaux,
recognizes that the C. G. T. is mild in comparison with the I. W. W. "The
I. W. W.," he says, "preach a policy of militant action, very necessary in
parts of America, which would not do in France."<SPAN href="#linknote-29"
name="linknoteref-29" id="linknoteref-29"><small>29</small></SPAN> A very
interesting account of it, from the point of view of an author who is
neither wholly on the side of labor nor wholly on the side of the
capitalist, but disinterestedly anxious to find some solution of the
social question short of violence and revolution, is the work of Mr. John
Graham Brooks, called "American Syndicalism: the I. W. W." (Macmillan,
1913). American labor conditions are very different from those of Europe.
In the first place, the power of the trusts is enormous; the concentration
of capital has in this respect proceeded more nearly on Marxian lines in
America than anywhere else. In the second place, the great influx of
foreign labor makes the whole problem quite different from any that arises
in Europe. The older skilled workers, largely American born, have long
been organized in the American Federation of Labor under Mr. Gompers.
These represent an aristocracy of labor. They tend to work with the
employers against the great mass of unskilled immigrants, and they cannot
be regarded as forming part of anything that could be truly called a labor
movement. "There are," says Mr. Cole, "now in America two working classes,
with different standards of life, and both are at present almost impotent
in the face of the employers. Nor is it possible for these two classes to
unite or to put forward any demands. . . . The American Federation of
Labor and the Industrial Workers of the World represent two different
principles of combination; but they also represent two different classes
of labor."<SPAN href="#linknote-30" name="linknoteref-30" id="linknoteref-30"><small>30</small></SPAN>
The I. W. W. stands for industrial unionism, whereas the American
Federation of Labor stands for craft unionism. The I. W. W. were formed in
1905 by a union of organizations, chief among which was the Western
Federation of Miners, which dated from 1892. They suffered a split by the
loss of the followers of Deleon, who was the leader of the "Socialist
Labor Party" and advocated a "Don't vote" policy, while reprobating
violent methods. The headquarters of the party which he formed are at
Detroit, and those of the main body are at Chicago. The I. W. W., though
it has a less definite philosophy than French Syndicalism, is quite
equally determined to destroy the capitalist system. As its secretary has
said: "There is but one bargain the I. W. W. will make with the employing
class— complete surrender of all control of industry to the
organized workers."<SPAN href="#linknote-31" name="linknoteref-31" id="linknoteref-31"><small>31</small></SPAN> Mr. Haywood, of the Western
Federation of Miners, is an out-and-out follower of Marx so far as
concerns the class war and the doctrine of surplus value. But, like all
who are in this movement, he attaches more importance to industrial as
against political action than do the European followers of Marx. This is
no doubt partly explicable by the special circumstances of America, where
the recent immigrants are apt to be voteless. The fourth convention of the
I. W. W. revised a preamble giving the general principles underlying its
action. "The working class and the employing class," they say, "have
nothing in common. There can be no peace so long as hunger and want are
found among millions of the working people and the few, who make up the
employing class, have all the good things of life. Between these two
classes, a struggle must go on until the workers of the world organize as
a class, take possession of the earth and the machinery of production, and
abolish the wage system. . . . Instead of the conservative motto, `A fair
day's wages for a fair day's work,' we must inscribe on our banner the
revolutionary watchword, `Abolition of the wage system.' "<SPAN href="#linknote-32" name="linknoteref-32" id="linknoteref-32"><small>32</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Numerous strikes have been conducted or encouraged by the I. W. W. and the
Western Federation of Miners. These strikes illustrate the class-war in a
more bitter and extreme form than is to be found in any other part of the
world. Both sides are always ready to resort to violence. The employers
have armies of their own and are able to call upon the Militia and even,
in a crisis, upon the United States Army. What French Syndicalists say
about the State as a capitalist institution is peculiarly true in America.
In consequence of the scandals thus arising, the Federal Government
appointed a Commission on Industrial Relations, whose Report, issued in
1915, reveals a state of affairs such as it would be difficult to imagine
in Great Britain. The report states that "the greatest disorders and most
of the outbreaks of violence in connection with industrial `disputes arise
from the violation of what are considered to be fundamental rights, and
from the perversion or subversion of governmental institutions" (p. 146).
It mentions, among such perversions, the subservience of the judiciary to
the mili- tary authorities, the fact that during a labor dispute the life
and liberty of every man within the State would seem to be at the mercy of
the Governor (p. 72), and the use of State troops in policing strikes (p.
298). At Ludlow (Colorado) in 1914 (April 20) a battle of the militia and
the miners took place, in which, as the result of the fire of the militia,
a number of women and children were burned to death.<SPAN href="#linknote-34"
name="linknoteref-34" id="linknoteref-34"><small>34</small></SPAN> Many other
instances of pitched battles could be given, but enough has been said to
show the peculiar character of labor disputes in the United States. It
may, I fear, be presumed that this character will remain so long as a very
large proportion of labor consists of recent immigrants. When these
difficulties pass away, as they must sooner or later, labor will more and
more find its place in the community, and will tend to feel and inspire
less of the bitter hostility which renders the more extreme forms of class
war possible. When</p>
<p>that time comes, the labor movement in America will probably begin to take
on forms similar to those of Europe.</p>
<p>Meanwhile, though the forms are different, the aims are very similar, and
industrial unionism, spreading from America, has had a considerable
influence in Great Britain—an influence naturally reinforced by that
of French Syndicalism. It is clear, I think, that the adoption of
industrial rather than craft unionism is absolutely necessary if Trade
Unionism is to succeed in playing that part in altering the economic
structure of society which its advocates claim for it rather than for the
political parties. Industrial unionism organizes men, as craft unionism
does not, in accordance with the enemy whom they have to fight. English
unionism is still very far removed from the industrial form, though
certain industries, especially the railway men, have gone very far in this
direction, and it is notable that the railway men are peculiarly
sympathetic to Syndicalism and industrial unionism.</p>
<p>Pure Syndicalism, however, is not very likely to achieve wide popularity
in Great Britain. Its spirit is too revolutionary and anarchistic for our
temperament. It is in the modified form of Guild Socialism that the ideas
derived from the C. G. T. and the I. W. W. are tending to bear fruit.<SPAN href="#linknote-35" name="linknoteref-35" id="linknoteref-35"><small>35</small></SPAN>
This movement is as yet in its infancy and has no great hold upon the rank
and file, but it is being ably advocated by a group of young men, and is
rapidly gaining ground among those who will form Labor opinion in years to
come. The power of the State has been so much increased during the war
that those who naturally dislike things as they are, find it more and more
difficult to believe that State omnipotence can be the road to the
millennium. Guild Socialists aim at autonomy in industry, with consequent
curtailment, but not abolition, of the power of the State. The system
which they advocate is, I believe, the best hitherto proposed, and the one
most likely to secure liberty without the constant appeals to violence
which are to be feared under a purely Anarchist regime.</p>
<p>The first pamphlet of the "National Guilds League" sets forth their main
principles. In industry each factory is to be free to control its own
methods of production by means of elected managers. The different
factories in a given industry are to be federated into a National Guild
which will deal with marketing and the general interests of the industry
as a whole. "The State would own the means of production as trustee for
the community; the Guilds would manage them, also as trustees for the
community, and would pay to the State a single tax or rent. Any Guild that
chose to set its own interests above those of the community would be
violating its trust, and would have to bow to the judgment of a tribunal
equally representing the whole body of producers and the whole body of
consumers. This Joint Committee would be the ultimate sovereign body, the
ultimate appeal court of industry. It would fix not only Guild taxation,
but also standard prices, and both taxation and prices would be
periodically readjusted by it." Each Guild will be entirely free to
apportion what it receives among its members as it chooses, its members
being all those who work in the industry which it covers. "The
distribution of this collective Guild income among the members seems to be
a matter for each Guild to decide for itself. Whether the Guilds would,
sooner or later, adopt the principle of equal payment for every member, is
open to discussion." Guild Socialism accepts from Syndicalism the view
that liberty is not to be secured by making the State the employer: "The
State and the Municipality as employers have turned out not to differ
essentially from the private capitalist." Guild Socialists regard the
State as consisting of the community in their capacity as consumers, while
the Guilds will represent them in their capacity as producers; thus
Parliament and the Guild Congress will be two co-equal powers representing
consumers and producers respectively. Above both will be the joint
Committee of Parliament and the Guild Congress for deciding matters
involving the interests of consumers and producers alike. The view of the
Guild Socialists is that State Socialism takes account of men only as
consumers, while Syndicalism takes account of them only as producers. "The
problem," say the Guild Socialists, "is to reconcile the two points of
view. That is what advocates of National Guilds set out to do. The
Syndicalist has claimed everything for the industrial organizations of
producers, the Collectivist everything for the territorial or political
organizations of consumers. Both are open to the same criticism; you
cannot reconcile two points of view merely by denying one of them."<SPAN href="#linknote-36" name="linknoteref-36" id="linknoteref-36"><small>36</small></SPAN>
But although Guild Socialism represents an attempt at readjustment between
two equally legitimate points of view, its impulse and force are derived
from what it has taken over from Syndicalism. Like Syndicalism; it desires
not primarily to make work better paid, but to secure this result along
with others by making it in itself more interesting and more democratic in
organization.</p>
<p>Capitalism has made of work a purely commercial activity, a soulless and a
joyless thing. But substitute the national service of the Guilds for the
profiteering of the few; substitute responsible labor for a saleable
commodity; substitute self-government and decentralization for the
bureaucracy and demoralizing hugeness of the modern State and the modern
joint stock company; and then it may be just once more to speak of a "joy
in labor," and once more to hope that men may be proud of quality and not
only of quantity in their work. There is a cant of the Middle Ages, and a
cant of "joy in labor," but it were better, perhaps, to risk that cant
than to reconcile ourselves forever to the philosophy of Capitalism and of
Collectivism, which declares that work is a necessary evil never to be
made pleasant, and that the workers' only hope is a leisure which shall be
longer, richer, and well adorned with municipal amenities.<SPAN href="#linknote-37" name="linknoteref-37" id="linknoteref-37"><small>37</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Although uniformly held that the writ of habeas corpus can only be
suspended by the legislature, in these labor disturbances the executive
has in fact suspended or disregarded the writ. . . . In cases arising from
labor agitations, the judiciary has uniformly upheld the power exercised
by the military, and in no case has there been any protest against the use
of such power or any attempt to curtail it, except in Montana, where the
conviction of a civilian by military commission was annulled" ("Final
Report of the Commission on Industrial Relations" (1915) appointed by the
United States Congress," p. 58).</p>
<p>Whatever may be thought of the practicability of Syndicalism, there is no
doubt that the ideas which it has put into the world have done a great
deal to revive the labor movement and to recall it to certain things of
fundamental importance which it had been in danger of forgetting.
Syndicalists consider man as producer rather than consumer. They are more
concerned to procure freedom in work than to increase material well-being.
They have revived the quest for liberty, which was growing somewhat dimmed
under the regime of Parliamentary Socialism, and they have reminded men
that what our modern society needs is not a little tinkering here and
there, nor the kind of minor readjustments to which the existing holders
of power may readily consent, but a fundamental reconstruction, a sweeping
away of all the sources of oppression, a liberation of men's constructive
energies, and a wholly new way of conceiving and regulating production and
economic relations. This merit is so great that, in view of it, all minor
defects become insignificant, and this merit Syndicalism will continue to
possess even if, as a definite movement, it should be found to have passed
away with the war.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_PART2" id="link2H_PART2"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> PART II — PROBLEMS OF THE FUTURE </h2>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0004" id="link2HCH0004"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER IV — WORK AND PAY </h2>
<p>THE man who seeks to create a better order of society has two resistances
to contend with: one that of Nature, the other that of his fellow-men.
Broadly speaking, it is science that deals with the resistance of Nature,
while politics and social organization are the methods of overcoming the
resistance of men.</p>
<p>The ultimate fact in economics is that Nature only yields commodities as
the result of labor. The necessity of SOME labor for the satisfaction of
our wants is not imposed by political systems or by the exploitation of
the working classes; it is due to physical laws, which the reformer, like
everyone else, must admit and study. Before any optimistic economic
project can be accepted as feasible, we must examine whether the physical
conditions of production impose an unalterable veto, or whether they are
capable of being sufficiently modified by science and organization. Two
connected doctrines must be considered in examining this question: First,
Malthus' doctrine of population; and second, the vaguer, but very
prevalent, view that any surplus above the bare necessaries of life can
only be produced if most men work long hours at monotonous or painful
tasks, leaving little leisure for a civilized existence or rational
enjoyment. I do not believe that either of these obstacles to optimism
will survive a close scrutiny. The possibility of technical improvement in
the methods of production is, I believe, so great that, at any rate for
centuries to come, there will be no inevitable barrier to progress in the
general well-being by the simultaneous increase of commodities and
diminution of hours of labor.</p>
<p>This subject has been specially studied by Kropotkin, who, whatever may be
thought of his general theories of politics, is remarkably instructive,
concrete and convincing in all that he says about the possibilities of
agriculture. Socialists and Anarchists in the main are products of
industrial life, and few among them have any practical knowledge on the
subject of food production. But Kropotkin is an exception. His two books,
"The Conquest of Bread" and "Fields, Factories and Workshops," are very
full of detailed information, and, even making great allowances for an
optimistic bias, I do not think it can be denied that they demonstrate
possibilities in which few of us would otherwise have believed.</p>
<p>Malthus contended, in effect, that population always tends to increase up
to the limit of subsistence, that the production of food becomes more
expensive as its amount is increased, and that therefore, apart from short
exceptional periods when new discoveries produce temporary alleviations,
the bulk of mankind must always be at the lowest level consistent with
survival and reproduction. As applied to the civilized races of the world,
this doctrine is becoming untrue through the rapid decline in the
birth-rate; but, apart from this decline, there are many other reasons why
the doctrine cannot be accepted, at any rate as regards the near future.
The century which elapsed after Malthus wrote, saw a very great increase
in the standard of comfort throughout the wage-earning classes, and, owing
to the enormous increase in the productivity of labor, a far greater rise
in the standard of comfort could have been effected if a more just system
of distribution had been introduced. In former times, when one man's labor
produced not very much more than was needed for one man's subsistence, it
was impossible either greatly to reduce the normal hours of labor, or
greatly to increase the proportion of the population who enjoyed more than
the bare necessaries of life. But this state of affairs has been overcome
by modern methods of production. At the present moment, not only do many
people enjoy a comfortable income derived from rent or interest, but about
half the population of most of the civilized countries in the world is
engaged, not in the production of commodities, but in fighting or in
manufacturing munitions of war. In a time of peace the whole of this half
might be kept in idleness without making the other half poorer than they
would have been if the war had continued, and if, instead of being idle,
they were productively employed, the whole of what they would produce
would be a divisible surplus over and above present wages. The present
productivity of labor in Great Britain would suffice to produce an income
of about 1 pound per day for each family, even without any of those
improvements in methods which are obviously immediately possible.</p>
<p>But, it will be said, as population increases, the price of food must
ultimately increase also as the sources of supply in Canada, the
Argentine, Australia and elsewhere are more and more used up. There must
come a time, so pessimists will urge, when food becomes so dear that the
ordinary wage-earner will have little surplus for expenditure upon other
things. It may be admitted that this would be true in some very distant
future if the population were to continue to increase without limit. If
the whole surface of the world were as densely populated as London is now,
it would, no doubt, require almost the whole labor of the population to
produce the necessary food from the few spaces remaining for agriculture.
But there is no reason to suppose that the population will continue to
increase indefinitely, and in any case the prospect is so remote that it
may be ignored in all practical considerations.</p>
<p>Returning from these dim speculations to the facts set forth by Kropotkin,
we find it proved in his writings that, by methods of intensive
cultivation, which are already in actual operation, the amount of food
produced on a given area can be increased far beyond anything that most
uninformed persons suppose possible. Speaking of the market-gardeners in
Great Britain, in the neighborhood of Paris, and in other places, he says:—</p>
<p>They have created a totally new agriculture. They smile when we boast
about the rotation system having permitted us to take from the field one
crop every year, or four crops each three years, because their ambition is
to have six and nine crops from the very same plot of land during the
twelve months. They do not understand our talk about good and bad soils,
because they make the soil themselves, and make it in such quantities as
to be compelled yearly to sell some of it; otherwise it would raise up the
level of their gardens by half an inch every year. They aim at cropping,
not five or six tons of grass on the acre, as we do, but from 50 to 100
tons of various vegetables on the same space; not 5 pound sworth of hay,
but 100 pounds worth of vegetables, of the plainest description, cabbage
and carrots.<SPAN href="#linknote-38" name="linknoteref-38" id="linknoteref-38"><small>38</small></SPAN></p>
<p>As regards cattle, he mentions that Mr. Champion at Whitby grows on each
acre the food of two or three head of cattle, whereas under ordinary high
farming it takes two or three acres to keep each head of cattle in Great
Britain. Even more astonishing are the achievements of the Culture
Maraicheres round Paris. It is impossible to summarize these achievements,
but we may note the general conclusion:—</p>
<p>There are now practical Maraichers who venture to maintain that if all the
food, animal and vegetable, necessary for the 3,500,000 inhabitants of the
Departments of Seine and Seine-et-Oise had to be grown on their own
territory (3250 square miles), it could be grown without resorting to any
other methods of culture than those already in use—methods already
tested on a large scale and proved successful.<SPAN href="#linknote-39"
name="linknoteref-39" id="linknoteref-39"><small>39</small></SPAN></p>
<p>It must be remembered that these two departments include the whole
population of Paris.</p>
<p>Kropotkin proceeds to point out methods by which the same result could be
achieved without long hours of labor. Indeed, he contends that the great
bulk of agricultural work could be carried on by people whose main
occupations are sedentary, and with only such a number of hours as would
serve to keep them in health and produce a pleasant diversification. He
protests against the theory of exces- sive division of labor. What he
wants is INTEGRATION, "a society where each individual is a producer of
both manual and intellectual work; where each able- bodied human being is
a worker, and where each worker works both in the field and in the
industrial workshop."<SPAN href="#linknote-40" name="linknoteref-40" id="linknoteref-40"><small>40</small></SPAN></p>
<p>These views as to production have no essential connection with Kropotkin's
advocacy of Anarchism. They would be equally possible under State
Socialism, and under certain circumstances they might even be carried out
in a capitalistic regime. They are important for our present purpose, not
from any argument which they afford in favor of one economic system as
against another, but from the fact that they remove the veto upon our
hopes which might otherwise result from a doubt as to the productive
capacity of labor. I have dwelt upon agriculture rather than industry,
since it is in regard to agriculture that the difficulties are chiefly
supposed to arise. Broadly speaking, industrial production tends to be
cheaper when it is carried on on a large scale, and therefore there is no
reason in industry why an increase in the demand should lead to an
increased cost of supply.</p>
<p>Passing now from the purely technical and material side of the problem of
production, we come to the human factor, the motives leading men to work,
the possibilities of efficient organization of production, and the
connection of production with distribution. Defenders of the existing
system maintain that efficient work would be impossible without the
economic stimulus, and that if the wage system were abolished men would
cease to do enough work to keep the community in tolerable comfort.
Through the alleged necessity of the economic motive, the problems of
production and distribution become intertwined. The desire for a more just
distribution of the world's goods is the main inspiration of most
Socialism and Anarchism. We must, therefore, consider whether the system
of distribution which they propose would be likely to lead to a diminished
production.</p>
<p>There is a fundamental difference between Socialism and Anarchism as
regards the question of distribution. Socialism, at any rate in most of
its forms, would retain payment for work done or for willingness to work,
and, except in the case of persons incapacitated by age or infirmity,
would make willingness to work a condition of subsistence, or at any rate
of subsistence above a certain very low minimum. Anarchism, on the other
hand, aims at granting to everyone, without any conditions whatever, just
as much of all ordinary commodities as he or she may care to consume,
while the rarer com- modities, of which the supply cannot easily be
indefinitely increased, would be rationed and divided equally among the
population. Thus Anarchism would not impose any OBLIGATIONS of work,
though Anarchists believe that the necessary work could be made
sufficiently agreeable for the vast majority of the population to
undertake it voluntarily. Socialists, on the other hand, would exact work.
Some of them would make the incomes of all workers equal, while others
would retain higher pay for the work which is considered more valuable.
All these different systems are compatible with the common ownership of
land and capital, though they differ greatly as regards the kind of
society which they would produce.</p>
<p>Socialism with inequality of income would not differ greatly as regards
the economic stimulus to work from the society in which we live. Such
differences as it would entail would undoubtedly be to the good from our
present point of view. Under the existing system many people enjoy
idleness and affluence through the mere accident of inheriting land or
capital. Many others, through their activities in industry or finance,
enjoy an income which is certainly very far in excess of anything to which
their social utility entitles them. On the other hand, it often happens
that inventors and discoverers, whose work has the very greatest social
utility, are robbed of their reward either by capitalists or by the
failure of the public to appreciate their work until too late. The better
paid work is only open to those who have been able to afford an expensive
training, and these men are selected in the main not by merit but by luck.
The wage earner is not paid for his willingness to work, but only for his
utility to the employer. Consequently, he may be plunged into destitution
by causes over which he has no control. Such destitution is a constant
fear, and when it occurs it produces undeserved suffering, and often
deterioration in the social value of the sufferer. These are a few among
the evils of our existing system from the standpoint of production. All
these evils we might expect to see remedied under any system of Socialism.</p>
<p>There are two questions which need to be considered when we are discussing
how far work requires the economic motive. The first question is: Must
society give higher pay for the more skilled or socially more valuable
work, if such work is to be done in sufficient quantities? The second
question is: Could work be made so attractive that enough of it would be
done even if idlers received just as much of the produce of work? The
first of these questions concerns the division between two schools of
Socialists: the more moderate Socialists sometimes concede that even under
Socialism it would be well to retain unequal pay for different kinds of
work, while the more thoroughgoing Socialists advocate equal incomes for
all workers. The second question, on the other hand, forms a division
between Socialists and Anarchists; the latter would not deprive a man of
commodities if he did not work, while the former in general would.</p>
<p>Our second question is so much more fundamental than our first that it
must be discussed at once, and in the course of this discussion what needs
to be said on our first question will find its place naturally.</p>
<p>Wages or Free Sharing?—"Abolition of the wages system" is one of the
watchwords common to Anarchists and advanced Socialists. But in its most
natural sense it is a watchword to which only the Anarchists have a right.
In the Anarchist conception of society all the commoner commodities will
be available to everyone without stint, in the kind of way in which water
is available at present.<SPAN href="#linknote-41" name="linknoteref-41" id="linknoteref-41"><small>41</small></SPAN> Advo- cates of this system point
out that it applies already to many things which formerly had to be paid
for, e.g., roads and bridges. They point out that it might very easily be
extended to trams and local trains. They proceed to argue—as
Kropotkin does by means of his proofs that the soil might be made
indefinitely more productive—that all the commoner kinds of food
could be given away to all who demanded them, since it would be easy to
produce them in quantities adequate to any possible demand. If this system
were extended to all the necessaries of life, everyone's bare livelihood
would be secured, quite regardless of the way in which he might choose to
spend his time. As for commodities which cannot be produced in indefinite
quantities, such as luxuries and delicacies, they also, according to the
Anarchists, are to be distributed without payment, but on a system of
rations, the amount available being divided equally among the population.
No doubt, though this is not said, something like a price will have to be
put upon these luxuries, so that a man may be free to choose how he will
take his share: one man will prefer good wine, another the finest Havana
cigars, another pictures or beautiful furniture. Presumably, every man
will be allowed to take such luxuries as are his due in whatever form he
prefers, the relative prices being fixed so as to equalize the demand. In
such a world as this, the economic stimulus to production will have wholly
disappeared, and if work is to continue it must be from other motives.<SPAN href="#linknote-42" name="linknoteref-42" id="linknoteref-42"><small>42</small></SPAN></p>
<p>Is such a system possible? First, is it technically possible to provide
the necessaries of life in such large quantities as would be needed if
every man and woman could take as much of them from the public stores as
he or she might desire?</p>
<p>The idea of purchase and payment is so familiar that the proposal to do
away with it must be thought at first fantastic. Yet I do not believe it
is nearly so fantastic as it seems. Even if we could all have bread for
nothing, we should not want more than a quite limited amount. As things
are, the cost of bread to the rich is so small a proportion of their
income as to afford practically no check upon their consumption; yet the
amount of bread that they consume could easily be supplied to the whole
population by improved methods of agriculture (I am not speaking of
war-time). The amount of food that people desire has natural limits, and
the waste that would be incurred would probably not be very great. As the
Anarchists point out, people at present enjoy an unlimited water supply
but very few leave the taps running when they are not using them. And one
may assume that public opinion would be opposed to excessive waste. We may
lay it down, I think, that the principle of unlimited supply could be
adopted in regard to all commodities for which the demand has limits that
fall short of what can be easily produced. And this would be the case, if
production were efficiently organized, with the necessaries of life,
including not only commodities, but also such things as education. Even if
all education were free up to the highest, young people, unless they were
radically transformed by the Anarchist regime, would not want more than a
certain amount of it. And the same applies to plain foods, plain clothes,
and the rest of the things that supply our elementary needs.</p>
<p>I think we may conclude that there is no technical impossibility in the
Anarchist plan of free sharing.</p>
<p>But would the necessary work be done if the individual were assured of the
general standard of comfort even though he did no work?</p>
<p>Most people will answer this question unhesitatingly in the negative.
Those employers in particular who are in the habit of denouncing their
employes as a set of lazy, drunken louts, will feel quite certain that no
work could be got out of them except under threat of dismissal and
consequent starvation. But is this as certain as people are inclined to
sup- pose at first sight? If work were to remain what most work is now, no
doubt it would be very hard to induce people to undertake it except from
fear of destitution. But there is no reason why work should remain the
dreary drudgery in horrible conditions that most of it is now.<SPAN href="#linknote-43" name="linknoteref-43" id="linknoteref-43"><small>43</small></SPAN>
If men had to be tempted to work instead of driven to it, the obvious
interest of the community would be to make work pleasant. So long as work
is not made on the whole pleasant, it cannot be said that anything like a
good state of society has been reached. Is the painfulness of work
unavoidable?</p>
<p>At present, the better paid work, that of the business and professional
classes, is for the most part enjoyable. I do not mean that every separate
moment is agreeable, but that the life of a man who has work of this sort
is on the whole happier than that of a man who enjoys an equal income
without doing any work. A certain amount of effort, and something in the
nature of a continuous career, are necessary to vigorous men if they are
to preserve their mental health and their zest for life. A considerable
amount of work is done without pay. People who take a rosy view of human
nature might have supposed that the duties of a magistrate would be among
disagreeable trades, like cleaning sewers; but a cynic might contend that
the pleasures of vindictiveness and moral superiority are so great that
there is no difficulty in finding well-to-do elderly gentlemen who are
willing, without pay, to send helpless wretches to the torture of prison.
And apart from enjoyment of the work itself, desire for the good opinion
of neighbors and for the feeling of effectiveness is quite sufficient to
keep many men active.</p>
<p>But, it will be said, the sort of work that a man would voluntarily choose
must always be exceptional: the great bulk of necessary work can never be
anything but painful. Who would choose, if an easy life were otherwise
open to him, to be a coal-miner, or a stoker on an Atlantic liner? I think
it must be conceded that much necessary work must always remain
disagreeable or at least painfully monotonous, and that special privileges
will have to be accorded to those who undertake it, if the Anarchist
system is ever to be made workable. It is true that the introduction of
such special privileges would somewhat mar the rounded logic of Anarchism,
but it need not, I think, make any really vital breach in its system. Much
of the work that needs doing could be rendered agreeable, if thought and
care were given to this object. Even now it is often only long hours that
make work irksome. If the normal hours of work were reduced to, say, four,
as they could be by better organization and more scientific methods, a
very great deal of work which is now felt as a burden would quite cease to
be so. If, as Kropotkin suggests, agricultural work, instead of being the
lifelong drudgery of an ignorant laborer living very near the verge of
abject poverty, were the occasional occupation of men and women normally
employed in industry or brain-work; if, instead of being conducted by
ancient traditional methods, without any possibility of intelligent
participation by the wage- earner, it were alive with the search for new
methods and new inventions, filled with the spirit of freedom, and
inviting the mental as well as the physical cooperation of those who do
the work, it might become a joy instead of a weariness, and a source of
health and life to those engaged in it.</p>
<p>What is true of agriculture is said by Anarchists to be equally true of
industry. They maintain that if the great economic organizations which are
now managed by capitalists, without consideration for the lives of the
wage-earners beyond what Trade Unions are able to exact, were turned
gradually into self-governing communities, in which the producers could
decide all questions of methods, conditions, hours of work, and so forth,
there would be an almost boundless change for the better: grime and noise
might be nearly eliminated, the hideousness of industrial regions might be
turned into beauty, the interest in the scientific aspects of production
might become diffused among all producers with any native intelligence,
and something of the artist's joy in creation might inspire the whole of
the work. All this, which is at present utterly remote from the reality,
might be produced by economic self-government. We may concede that by such
means a very large proportion of the necessary work of the world could
ultimately be made sufficiently agreeable to be preferred before idleness
even by men whose bare livelihood would be assured whether they worked or
not. As to the residue let us admit that special rewards, whether in goods
or honors or privileges, would have to be given to those who undertook it.
But this need not cause any fundamental objection.</p>
<p>There would, of course, be a certain proportion of the population who
would prefer idleness. Provided the proportion were small, this need not
matter. And among those who would be classed as idlers might be included
artists, writers of books, men devoted to abstract intellectual pursuits—in
short, all those whom society despises while they are alive and honors
when they are dead. To such men, the possibility of pursuing their own
work regardless of any public recognition of its utility would be
invaluable. Whoever will observe how many of our poets have been men of
private means will realize how much poetic capacity must have remained
undeveloped through poverty; for it would be absurd to suppose that the
rich are better endowed by nature with the capacity for poetry. Freedom
for such men, few as they are, must be set against the waste of the mere
idlers.</p>
<p>So far, we have set forth the arguments in favor of the Anarchist plan.
They are, to my mind, sufficient to make it seem possible that the plan
might succeed, but not sufficient to make it so probable that it would be
wise to try it.</p>
<p>The question of the feasibility of the Anarchist proposals in regard to
distribution is, like so many other questions, a quantitative one. The
Anarchist proposals consist of two parts: (1) That all the common
commodities should be supplied ad lib. to all applicants; (2) That no
obligation to work, or economic reward for work, should be imposed on
anyone. These two proposals are not necessarily inseparable, nor does
either entail the whole system of Anarchism, though without them Anarchism
would hardly be possible. As regards the first of these proposals, it can
be carried out even now with regard to some commodities, and it could be
carried out in no very distant future with regard to many more. It is a
flexible plan, since this or that article of consumption could be placed
on the free list or taken of as circumstances might dictate. Its
advantages are many and various, and the practice of the world tends to
develop in this direction. I think we may conclude that this part of the
Anarchists' system might well be adopted bit by bit, reaching gradually
the full extension that they desire.</p>
<p>But as regards the second proposal, that there should be no obligation to
work, and no economic reward for work, the matter is much more doubtful.
Anarchists always assume that if their schemes were put into operation
practically everyone would work; but although there is very much more to
be said for this view than most people would concede at first sight, yet
it is questionable whether there is enough to be said to make it true for
practical purposes. Perhaps, in a community where industry had become
habitual through economic pressure, public opinion might be sufficiently
powerful to compel most men to work;<SPAN href="#linknote-44"
name="linknoteref-44" id="linknoteref-44"><small>44</small></SPAN> but it is
always doubtful how far such a state of things would be permanent. If
public opinion is to be really effective, it will be necessary to have
some method of dividing the community into small groups, and to allow each
group to consume only the equivalent of what it produces. This will make
the economic motive operative upon the group, which, since we are
supposing it small, will feel that its collective share is appreciably
diminished by each idle individual. Such a system might be feasible, but
it would be contrary to the whole spirit of Anarchism and would destroy
the main lines of its economic system.</p>
<p>The attitude of orthodox Socialism on this question is quite different
from that of Anarchism.<SPAN href="#linknote-45" name="linknoteref-45" id="linknoteref-45"><small>45</small></SPAN> Among the more immediate
measures advocated in the "Communist Manifesto" is "equal liability of all
to labor. Establishment of industrial armies, especially for agriculture."
The Socialist theory is that, in general, work alone gives the right to
the enjoyment of the produce of work. To this theory there will, of
course, be exceptions: the old and the very young, the infirm and those
whose work is temporarily not required through no fault of their own. But
the fundamental conception of Socialism, in regard to our present
question, is that all who can should be compelled to work, either by the
threat of starvation or by the operation of the criminal law. And, of
course, the only kind of work recognized will be such as commends itself
to the authorities. Writing books against Socialism, or against any theory
embodied in the government of the day, would certainly not be recognized
as work. No more would the painting of pictures in a different style from
that of the Royal Academy, or producing plays unpleasing to the censor.
Any new line of thought would be banned, unless by influence or corruption
the thinker could crawl into the good graces of the pundits. These results
are not foreseen by Socialists, because they imagine that the Socialist
State will be governed by men like those who now advocate it. This is, of
course, a delusion. The rulers of the State then will bear as little
resemblance to the pres- ent Socialists as the dignitaries of the Church
after the time of Constantine bore to the Apostles. The men who advocate
an unpopular reform are exceptional in disinterestedness and zeal for the
public good; but those who hold power after the reform has been carried
out are likely to belong, in the main, to the ambitious executive type
which has in all ages possessed itself of the government of nations. And
this type has never shown itself tolerant of opposition or friendly to
freedom.</p>
<p>It would seem, then, that if the Anarchist plan has its dangers, the
Socialist plan has at least equal dangers. It is true that the evils we
have been foreseeing under Socialism exist at present, but the purpose of
Socialists is to cure the evils of the world as it is; they cannot be
content with the argument that they would make things no worse.</p>
<p>Anarchism has the advantage as regards liberty, Socialism as regards the
inducements to work. Can we not find a method of combining these two
advantages? It seems to me that we can.</p>
<p>We saw that, provided most people work in moderation, and their work is
rendered as productive as science and organization can make it, there is
no good reason why the necessaries of life should not be supplied freely
to all. Our only serious doubt was as to whether, in an Anarchist regime,
the motives for work would be sufficiently powerful to prevent a dan-
gerously large amount of idleness. But it would be easy to decree that,
though necessaries should be free to all, whatever went beyond necessaries
should only be given to those who were willing to work—not, as is
usual at present, only to those in work at any moment, but also to all
those who, when they happened not to be working, were idle through no
fault of their own. We find at present that a man who has a small income
from investments, just sufficient to keep him from actual want, almost
always prefers to find some paid work in order to be able to afford
luxuries. So it would be, presumably, in such a community as we are
imagining. At the same time, the man who felt a vocation for some
unrecognized work of art or science or thought would be free to follow his
desire, provided he were willing to "scorn delights and live laborious
days." And the comparatively small number of men with an invincible horror
of work—the sort of men who now become tramps— might lead a
harmless existence, without any grave danger of their becoming
sufficiently numerous to be a serious burden upon the more industrious. In
this ways the claims of freedom could be combined with the need of some
economic stimulus to work. Such a system, it seems to me, would have a far
greater chance of success than either pure Anarchism or pure orthodox
Socialism.</p>
<p>Stated in more familiar terms, the plan we are advocating amounts
essentially to this: that a certain small income, sufficient for
necessaries, should be secured to all, whether they work or not, and that
a larger income, as much larger as might be warranted by the total amount
of commodities produced, should be given to those who are willing to
engage in some work which the community recognizes as useful. On this
basis we may build further. I do not think it is always necessary to pay
more highly work which is more skilled or regarded as socially more
useful, since such work is more interesting and more respected than
ordinary work, and will therefore often be preferred by those who are able
to do it. But we might, for instance, give an intermediate income to those
who are only willing to work half the usual number of hours, and an income
above that of most workers to those who choose a specially disagreeable
trade. Such a system is perfectly compatible with Socialism, though
perhaps hardly with Anarchism. Of its advantages we shall have more to say
at a later stage. For the present I am content to urge that it combines
freedom with justice, and avoids those dangers to the community which we
have found to lurk both in the proposals of the Anarchists and in those of
orthodox Socialists.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0005" id="link2HCH0005"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER V — GOVERNMENT AND LAW </h2>
<p>GOVERNMENT and Law, in their very essence, consist of restrictions on
freedom, and freedom is the greatest of political goods.<SPAN href="#linknote-46" name="linknoteref-46" id="linknoteref-46"><small>46</small></SPAN>
A hasty reasoner might conclude without further ado that Law and
government are evils which must be abolished if freedom is our goal. But
this consequence, true or false, cannot be proved so simply. In this
chapter we shall examine the arguments of Anarchists against law and the
State. We shall proceed on the assumption that freedom is the supreme aim
of a good social system; but on this very basis we shall find the
Anarchist contentions very questionable.</p>
<p>Respect for the liberty of others is not a natural impulse with most men:
envy and love of power lead ordinary human nature to find pleasure in
interferences with the lives of others. If all men's actions were wholly
unchecked by external authority, we should not obtain a world in which all
men would be free. The strong would oppress the weak, or the majority
would oppress the minority, or the lovers of violence would oppress the
more peaceable people. I fear it cannot be said that these bad impulses
are WHOLLY due to a bad social system, though it must be conceded that the
present competitive organization of society does a great deal to foster
the worst elements in human nature. The love of power is an impulse which,
though innate in very ambitious men, is chiefly promoted as a rule by the
actual experience of power. In a world where none could acquire much
power, the desire to tyrannize would be much less strong than it is at
present. Nevertheless, I cannot think that it would be wholly absent, and
those in whom it would exist would often be men of unusual energy and
executive capacity. Such men, if they are not restrained by the organized
will of the community, may either succeed in establishing a despotism, or,
at any rate, make such a vigorous attempt as can only be defeated through
a period of prolonged disturbance. And apart from the love or political
power, there is the love of power over individuals. If threats and
terrorism were not prevented by law, it can hardly be doubted that cruelty
would be rife in the relations of men and women, and of parents and
children. It is true that the habits of a community can make such cruelty
rare, but these habits, I fear, are only to be produced through the
prolonged reign of law. Experience of backwoods communities, mining camps
and other such places seems to show that under new conditions men easily
revert to a more barbarous attitude and practice. It would seem,
therefore, that, while human nature remains as it is, there will be more
liberty for all in a community where some acts of tyranny by individuals
are forbidden, than in a community where the law leaves each individual
free to follow his every impulse. But, although the necessity of some form
of government and law must for the present be conceded, it is important to
remember that all law and government is in itself in some degree an evil,
only justifiable when it prevents other and greater evils. Every use of
the power of the State needs, therefore, to be very closely scrutinized,
and every possibility of diminishing its power is to be welcomed provided
it does not lead to a reign of private tyranny.</p>
<p>The power of the State is partly legal, partly economic: acts of a kind
which the State dislikes can be punished by the criminal law, and
individuals who incur the displeasure of the State may find it hard to
earn a livelihood.</p>
<p>The views of Marx on the State are not very clear. On the one hand he
seems willing,, like the modern State Socialists, to allow great power to
the State, but on the other hand he suggests that when the Socialist
revolution has been consummated, the State, as we know it, will disappear.
Among the measures which are advocated in the Communist Manifesto as
immediately desirable, there are several which would very greatly increase
the power of the existing State. For example, "Centralization of credit in
the hands of the State, by means of a national bank with State capital and
an exclusive monopoly;" and again, "Centralization of the means of
communication and transport in the hands of the State." But the Manifesto
goes on to say:</p>
<p>When, in the course of development, class distinctions have disappeared,
and all production has been concentrated in the hands of a vast
association of the whole nation, the public power will lose its political
character. Political power, properly so called, is merely the organised
power of one class for oppressing another. If the proletariat during its
contest with the bourgeoisie is compelled, by the force of circumstances,
to organize itself as a class, if, by means of a revolution, it makes
itself the ruling class, and, as such, sweeps away by force the old
conditions of production, then it will, along with these conditions, have
swept away the conditions for the existence of class antagonisms, and of
classes generally, and will thereby have abolished its own supremacy as a
class.</p>
<p>In place of the old bourgeois society, with its classes and class
antagonisms, we shall have an association, in which; the free development
of each is the condition for the free development of all.<SPAN href="#linknote-47" name="linknoteref-47" id="linknoteref-47"><small>47</small></SPAN></p>
<p>This attitude Marx preserved in essentials throughout his life.
Accordingly, it is not to be wondered at that his followers, so far as
regards their immediate aims, have in the main become out-and-out State
Socialists. On the other hand, the Syndicalists, who accept from Marx the
doctrine of the class war, which they regard as what is really vital in
his teaching, reject the State with abhorrence and wish to abolish it
wholly, in which respect they are at one with the Anarchists. The Guild
Socialists, though some persons in this country regard them as extremists,
really represent the English love of compromise. The Syndicalist arguments
as to the dangers inherent in the power of the State have made them
dissatisfied with the old State Socialism, but they are unable to accept
the Anarchist view that society can dispense altogether with a central
authority. Accordingly they propose that there should be two co-equal
instruments of Government in a community, the one geographical,
representing the consumers, and essentially the continuation of the
democratic State; the other representing the producers, organized, not
geographically, but in guilds, after the manner of industrial unionism.
These two author- ities will deal with different classes of questions.
Guild Socialists do not regard the industrial authority as forming part of
the State, for they contend that it is the essence of the State to be
geographical; but the industrial authority will resemble the present State
in the fact that it will have coercive powers, and that its decrees will
be enforced, when necessary. It is to be suspected that Syndicalists also,
much as they object to the existing State, would not object to coercion of
individuals in an industry by the Trade Union in that industry. Government
within the Trade Union would probably be quite as strict as State
government is now. In saying this we are assuming that the theoretical
Anarchism of Syndicalist leaders would not survive accession to power, but
I am afraid experience shows that this is not a very hazardous assumption.</p>
<p>Among all these different views, the one which raises the deepest issue is
the Anarchist contention that all coercion by the community is
unnecessary. Like most of the things that Anarchists say, there is much
more to be urged in support of this view than most people would suppose at
first sight. Kropotkin, who is its ablest exponent, points out how much
has been achieved already by the method of free agreement. He does not
wish to abolish government in the sense of collective decisions: what he
does wish to abolish is the system by which a decision is en- forced upon
those who oppose it.<SPAN href="#linknote-48" name="linknoteref-48" id="linknoteref-48"><small>48</small></SPAN> The whole system of
representative government and majority rule is to him a bad thing.<SPAN href="#linknote-49" name="linknoteref-49" id="linknoteref-49"><small>49</small></SPAN>
He points to such instances as the agreements among the different railway
systems of the Continent for the running of through expresses and for
co-operation generally. He points out that in such cases the different
companies or authorities concerned each appoint a delegate, and that the
delegates suggest a basis of agreement, which has to be subsequently
ratified by each of the bodies ap- pointing them. The assembly of
delegates has no coercive power whatever, and a majority can do nothing
against a recalcitrant minority. Yet this has not prevented the conclusion
of very elaborate systems of agreements. By such methods, so Anarchists
contend, the USEFUL functions of government can be carried out without any
coercion. They maintain that the usefulness of agreement is so patent as
to make co-operation certain if once the predatory motives associated with
the present system of private property were removed.</p>
<p>"It seems to me, however, that State and government represent two ideas of
a different kind. The State idea implies quite another idea to that of
government. It not only includes the existence of a power placed above
society, but also a territorial concentration and a concentration of many
functions of the life of society in the hands of a few or even of all. It
implies new relations among the members of society.</p>
<p>"This characteristic distinction, which perhaps escapes notice at first
sight, appears clearly when the origin of the State is studied."
Kropotkin, "The State." p. 4.</p>
<p>Attractive as this view is, I cannot resist the conclusion that it results
from impatience and represents the attempt to find a short-cut toward the
ideal which all humane people desire.</p>
<p>Let us begin with the question of private crime.<SPAN href="#linknote-50"
name="linknoteref-50" id="linknoteref-50"><small>50</small></SPAN> Anarchists
maintain that the criminal is manufactured by bad social conditions and
would disappear in such a world as they aim at creating.<SPAN href="#linknote-51" name="linknoteref-51" id="linknoteref-51"><small>51</small></SPAN>
No doubt there is a great measure of truth in this view. There would be
little motive to robbery, for example, in an Anarchist world, unless it
were organized on a large scale by a body of men bent on upsetting the
Anarchist regime. It may also be conceded that impulses toward criminal
violence could be very largely eliminated by a better education. But all
such contentions, it seems to me, have their limitations. To take an
extreme case, we cannot suppose that there would be no lunatics in an
Anarchist community, and some of these lunatics would, no doubt, be
homicidal. Probably no one would argue that they ought to be left at
liberty. But there are no sharp lines in nature; from the homicidal
lunatic to the sane man of violent passions there is a continuous
gradation. Even in the most perfect community there will be men and women,
otherwise sane, who will feel an impulse to commit murder from jealousy.
These are now usually restrained by the fear of punishment, but if this
fear were removed, such murders would probably become much more common, as
may be seen from the present behavior of certain soldiers on leave.
Moreover, certain kinds of conduct arouse public hostility, and would
almost inevitably lead to lynching, if no other recognized method of
punishment existed. There is in most men a certain natural vindictiveness,
not always directed against the worst members of the community. For
example, Spinoza was very nearly murdered by the mob because he was
suspected of undue friendliness to France at a time when Holland was at
war with that country. Apart from such cases, there would be the very real
danger of an organized attempt to destroy Anarchism and revive ancient
oppressions. Is it to be supposed, for example, that Napoleon, if he had
been born into such a community as Kropotkin advocates, would have
acquiesced tamely in a world where his genius could find no scope? I
cannot see what should prevent a combination of ambitious men forming
themselves into a private army, manufacturing their own munitions, and at
last enslaving the defenseless citizens, who had relied upon the inherent
attractiveness of liberty. It would not be consistent with the principles
of Anarchism for the community to interfere with the drilling of a private
army, no matter what its objects might be (though, of course, an opposing
private army might be formed by men with different views). Indeed,
Kropotkin instances the old volunteers in Great Britain as an example of a
movement on Anarchist lines.<SPAN href="#linknote-52" name="linknoteref-52" id="linknoteref-52"><small>52</small></SPAN> Even if a predatory army were
not formed from within, it might easily come from a neighboring nation, or
from races on the borderland of civilization. So long as the love of power
exists, I do not see how it can be prevented from finding an outlet in
oppression except by means of the organized force of the community.</p>
<p>The conclusion, which appears to be forced upon us, is that the Anarchist
ideal of a community in which no acts are forbidden by law is not, at any
rate for the present, compatible with the stability of such a world as the
Anarchists desire. In order to obtain and preserve a world resembling as
closely as possible that at which they aim, it will still be necessary
that some acts should be forbidden by law. We may put the chief of these
under three heads:</p>
<p>1. Theft.</p>
<p>2. Crimes of violence.</p>
<p>3. The creation of organizations intended to subvert the Anarchist regime
by force.</p>
<p>We will briefly recapitulate what has been said already as to the
necessity of these prohibitions.</p>
<p>1. Theft.—It is true that in an Anarchist world there will be no
destitution, and therefore no thefts motivated by starvation. But such
thefts are at present by no means the most considerable or the most
harmful. The system of rationing, which is to be applied to luxuries, will
leave many men with fewer luxuries than they might desire. It will give
opportunities for peculation by those who are in control of the public
stores, and it will leave the possibility of appropriating such valuable
objects of art as would naturally be preserved in public museums. It may
be contended that such forms of theft would be prevented by public
opinion. But public opinion is not greatly operative upon an individual
unless it is the opinion of his own group. A group of men combined for
purposes of theft might readily defy the public opinion of the majority
unless that public opinion made itself effective by the use of force
against them. Probably, in fact, such force would be applied through
popular indignation, but in that case we should revive the evils of the
criminal law with the added evils of uncertainty, haste and passion, which
are inseparable from the practice of lynching. If, as we have suggested,
it were found necessary to provide an economic stimulus to work by
allowing fewer luxuries to idlers, this would afford a new motive for
theft on their part and a new necessity for some form of criminal law.</p>
<p>2. Crimes of Violence.—Cruelty to children, crimes of jealousy,
rape, and so forth, are almost certain to occur in any society to some
extent. The prevention of such acts is essential to the existence of
freedom for the weak. If nothing were done to hinder them, it is to be
feared that the customs of a society would gradually become rougher, and
that acts which are now rare would cease to be so. If Anarchists are right
in maintaining that the existence of such an economic system as they
desire would prevent the commission of crimes of this kind, the laws
forbidding them would no longer come into operation, and would do no harm
to liberty. If, on the other hand, the impulse to such actions persisted,
it would be necessary that steps should be taken to restrain men from
indulging it.</p>
<p>3. The third class of difficulties is much the most serious and involves
much the most drastic interference with liberty. I do not see how a
private army could be tolerated within an Anarchist community, and I do
not see how it could be prevented except by a general prohibition of
carrying arms. If there were no such prohibition, rival parties would
organize rival forces, and civil war would result. Yet, if there is such a
prohibition, it cannot well be carried out without a very considerable
interference with individual liberty. No doubt, after a time, the idea of
using violence to achieve a political object might die down, as the
practice of duelling has done. But such changes of habit and outlook are
facilitated by legal prohibition, and would hardly come about without it.
I shall not speak yet of the international aspect of this same problem,
for I propose to deal with that in the next chapter, but it is clear that
the same considerations apply with even greater force to the relations
between nations.</p>
<p>If we admit, however reluctantly, that a criminal law is necessary and
that the force of the community must be brought to bear to prevent certain
kinds of actions, a further question arises: How is crime to be treated?
What is the greatest measure of humanity and respect for freedom that is
compatible with the recognition of such a thing as crime? The first thing
to recognize is that the whole conception of guilt or sin should be
utterly swept away. At present, the criminal is visited with the
displeasure of the community: the sole method applied to prevent the
occurrence of crime is the infliction of pain upon the criminal.
Everything possible is done to break his spirit and destroy his
self-respect. Even those pleasures which would be most likely to have a
civilizing effect are forbidden to him, merely on the ground that they are
pleasures, while much of the suffering inflicted is of a kind which can
only brutalize and degrade still further. I am not speaking, of course, of
those few penal institutions which have made a serious study of reforming
the criminal. Such institutions, especially in America, have been proved
capable of achieving the most remarkable results, but they remain
everywhere exceptional. The broad rule is still that the criminal is made
to feel the displeasure of society. He must emerge from such a treatment
either defiant and hostile, or submissive and cringing, with a broken
spirit and a loss of self-respect. Neither of these results is anything
but evil. Nor can any good result be achieved by a method of treatment
which embodies reprobation.</p>
<p>When a man is suffering from an infectious disease he is a danger to the
community, and it is necessary to restrict his liberty of movement. But no
one associates any idea of guilt with such a situation. On the contrary,
he is an object of commiseration to his friends. Such steps as science
recommends are taken to cure him of his disease, and he submits as a rule
without reluctance to the curtailment of liberty involved meanwhile. The
same method in spirit ought to be shown in the treatment of what is called
"crime." It is supposed, of course, that the criminal is actuated by
calculations of self-interest, and that the fear of punishment, by
supplying a contrary motive of self-interest affords the best deterrent,</p>
<p>The dog, to gain some private end,<br/>
Went mad and bit the man.<br/></p>
<p>This is the popular view of crime; yet no dog goes mad from choice, and
probably the same is true of the great majority of criminals, certainly in
the case of crimes of passion. Even in cases where self-interest is the
motive, the important thing is to prevent the crime, not to make the
criminal suffer. Any suffering which may be entailed by the process of
prevention ought to be regarded as regrettable, like the pain involved in
a surgical operation. The man who commits a crime from an impulse to
violence ought to be subjected to a scientific psychological treatment,
designed to elicit more beneficial impulses. The man who commits a crime
from calculations of self- interest ought to be made to feel that
self-interest itself, when it is fully understood, can be better served by
a life which is useful to the community than by one which is harmful. For
this purpose it is chiefly necessary to widen his outlook and increase the
scope of his desires. At present, when a man suffers from insufficient
love for his fellow-creatures, the method of curing him which is commonly
adopted seems scarcely designed to succeed, being, indeed, in essentials,
the same as his attitude toward them. The object of the prison
administration is to save trouble, not to study the individual case. He is
kept in captivity in a cell from which all sight of the earth is shut out:
he is subjected to harshness by warders, who have too often become
brutalized by their occupation.<SPAN href="#linknote-53" name="linknoteref-53" id="linknoteref-53"><small>53</small></SPAN> He is solemnly denounced as an
enemy to society. He is compelled to perform mechanical tasks, chosen for
their wearisomeness. He is given no education and no incentive to
self-improvement. Is it to be wondered at if, at the end of such a course
of treatment, his feelings toward the community are no more friendly than
they were at the beginning?</p>
<p>Severity of punishment arose through vindictiveness and fear in an age
when many criminals escaped justice altogether, and it was hoped that
savage sentences would outweigh the chance of escape in the mind of the
criminal. At present a very large part of the criminal law is concerned in
safeguarding the rights of property, that is to say—as things are
now—the unjust privileges of the rich. Those whose principles lead
them into conflict with government, like Anarchists, bring a most
formidable indictment against the law and the authorities for the unjust
manner in which they support the status quo. Many of the actions by which
men have become rich are far more harmful to the community than the
obscure crimes of poor men, yet they go unpunished because they do not
interfere with the existing order. If the power of the community is to be
brought to bear to prevent certain classes of actions through the agency
of the criminal law, it is as necessary that these actions should really
be those which are harmful to the community, as it is that the treatment
of "criminals" should be freed from the conception of guilt and inspired
by the same spirit as is shown in the treatment of disease. But, if these
two conditions were fulfilled, I cannot help thinking that a society which
preserved the existence of law would be preferable to one conducted on the
unadulterated principles of Anarchism.</p>
<p>So far we have been considering the power which the State derives from the
criminal law. We have every reason to think that this power cannot be
entirely abolished, though it can be exercised in a wholly different
spirit, without the vindictiveness and the moral reprobation which now
form its essence.</p>
<p>We come next to the consideration of the economic power of the State and
the influence which it can exert through its bureaucracy. State Socialists
argue as if there would be no danger to liberty in a State not based upon
capitalism. This seems to me an entire delusion. Given an official caste,
however selected, there are bound to be a set of men whose whole instincts
will drive them toward tyranny. Together with the natural love of power,
they will have a rooted conviction (visible now in the higher ranks of the
Civil Service) that they alone know enough to be able to judge what is for
the good of the community. Like all men who administer a system, they will
come to feel the system itself sacrosanct. The only changes they will
desire will be changes in the direction of further regulations as to how
the people are to enjoy the good things kindly granted to them by their
benevolent despots. Whoever thinks this picture overdrawn must have failed
to study the influence and methods of Civil Servants at present. On every
matter that arises, they know far more than the general public about all
the DEFINITE facts involved; the one thing they do not know is "where the
shoe pinches." But those who know this are probably not skilled in stating
their case, not able to say off-hand exactly how many shoes are pinching
how many feet, or what is the precise remedy required. The answer prepared
for Ministers by the Civil Service is accepted by the "respectable" public
as impartial, and is regarded as disposing of the case of malcontents
except on a first-class political question on which elections may be won
or lost. That at least is the way in which things are managed in England.
And there is every reason to fear that under State Socialism the power of
officials would be vastly greater than it is at present.</p>
<p>Those who accept the orthodox doctrine of democracy contend that, if ever
the power of capital were removed, representative institutions would
suffice to undo the evils threatened by bureaucracy. Against this view,
Anarchists and Syndicalists have directed a merciless criticism. French
Syndicalists especially, living, as they do, in a highly democratized
country, have had bitter experience of the way in which the power of the
State can be employed against a progressive minority. This experience has
led them to abandon altogether the belief in the divine right of
majorities. The Constitution that they would desire would be one which
allowed scope for vigorous minorities, conscious of their aims and
prepared to work for them. It is undeniable that, to all who care for
progress, actual experience of democratic representative Government is
very disillusioning. Admitting— as I think we must—that it is
preferable to any PREVIOUS form of Government, we must yet acknowledge
that much of the criticism directed against it by Anarchists and
Syndicalists is thoroughly justified.</p>
<p>Such criticism would have had more influence if any clear idea of an
alternative to parliamentary democracy had been generally apprehended. But
it must be confessed that Syndicalists have not presented their case in a
way which is likely to attract the average citizen. Much of what they say
amounts to this: that a minority, consisting of skilled workers in vital
industries, can, by a strike, make the economic life of the whole
community impossible, and can in this way force their will upon the
nation. The action aimed at is compared to the seizure of a power station,
by which a whole vast system can be paralyzed. Such a doctrine is an
appeal to force, and is naturally met by an appeal to force on the other
side. It is useless for the Syndicalists to protest that they only desire
power in order to promote liberty: the world which they are seeking to
establish does not, as yet, appeal to the effective will of the community,
and cannot be stably inaugurated until it does do so. Persuasion is a slow
process, and may sometimes be accelerated by violent methods; to this
extent such methods may be justified. But the ultimate goal of any
reformer who aims at liberty can only be reached through persuasion. The
attempt to thrust liberty by force upon those who do not desire what we
consider liberty must always prove a failure; and Syndicalists, like other
reformers, must ultimately rely upon persuasion for success.</p>
<p>But it would be a mistake to confuse aims with methods: however little we
may agree with the proposal to force the millennium on a reluctant
community by starvation, we may yet agree that much of what the
Syndicalists desire to achieve is desirable.</p>
<p>Let us dismiss from our minds such criticisms of parliamentary government
as are bound up with the present system of private property, and consider
only those which would remain true in a collectivist community. Certain
defects seem inherent in the very nature of representative institutions.
There is a sense of self-importance, inseparable from success in a contest
for popular favor. There is an all-but unavoidable habit of hypocrisy,
since experience shows that the democracy does not detect insincerity in
an orator, and will, on the other hand, be shocked by things which even
the most sincere men may think necessary. Hence arises a tone of cynicism
among elected representatives, and a feeling that no man can retain his
position in politics without deceit. This is as much the fault of the
democracy as of the representatives, but it seems unavoidable so long as
the main thing that all bodies of men demand of their champions is
flattery. However the blame may be apportioned, the evil must be
recognized as one which is bound to occur in the existing forms of
democracy. Another evil, which is especially noticeable in large States,
is the remoteness of the seat of government from many of the
constituencies—a remoteness which is psychological even more than
geographical. The legislators live in comfort, protected by thick walls
and innumerable policemen from the voice of the mob; as time goes on they
remember only dimly the passions and promises of their electoral campaign;
they come to feel it an essential part of statesmanship to consider what
are called the interests of the community as a whole, rather than those of
some discontented group; but the interests of the community as a whole are
sufficiently vague to be easily seen to coincide with self-interest. All
these causes lead Parliaments to betray the people, consciously or
unconsciously; and it is no wonder if they have produced a certain
aloofness from democratic theory in the more vigorous champions of labor.</p>
<p>Majority rule, as it exists in large States, is subject to the fatal
defect that, in a very great number of questions, only a fraction of the
nation have any direct interest or knowledge, yet the others have an equal
voice in their settlement. When people have no direct interest in a
question they are very apt to be influenced by irrelevant considerations;
this is shown in the extraordinary reluctance to grant autonomy to
subordinate nations or groups. For this reason, it is very dangerous to
allow the nation as a whole to decide on matters which concern only a
small section, whether that section be geographical or industrial or
defined in any other way. The best cure for this evil, so far as can be
seen at present, lies in allowing self-government to every important group
within a nation in all matters that affect that group much more than they
affect the rest of the community. The government of a group, chosen by the
group, will be far more in touch with its constituents, far more conscious
of their interests, than a remote Parliament nominally representing the
whole country. The most original idea in Syndicalism— adopted and
developed by the Guild Socialists—is the idea of making industries
self-governing units so far as their internal affairs are concerned. By
this method, extended also to such other groups as have clearly separable
interests, the evils which have shown themselves in representative
democracy can, I believe, be largely overcome.</p>
<p>Guild Socialists, as we have seen, have another suggestion, growing
naturally out of the autonomy of industrial guilds, by which they hope to
limit the power of the State and help to preserve individual liberty. They
propose that, in addition to Parliament, elected (as at present) on a
territorial basis and representing the community as consumers, there shall
also be a "Guild Congress," a glorified successor of the present Trade
Union Congress, which shall consist of representatives chosen by the
Guilds, and shall represent the community as producers.</p>
<p>This method of diminishing the excessive power of the State has been
attractively set forth by Mr. G. D. H. Cole in his "Self-Government in
Industry."<SPAN href="#linknote-54" name="linknoteref-54" id="linknoteref-54"><small>54</small></SPAN>
"Where now," he says, "the State passes a Factory Act, or a Coal Mines
Regulation Act, the Guild Congress of the future will pass such Acts, and
its power of enforcing them will be the same as that of the State" (p.
98). His ultimate ground for advocating this system is that, in his
opinion, it will tend to preserve individual liberty: "The fundamental
reason for the preservation, in a democratic Society, of both the
industrial and the political forms of Social organization is, it seems to
me, that only by dividing the vast power now wielded by industrial
capitalism can the individual hope to be free" (p. 91).</p>
<p>Will the system suggested by Mr. Cole have this result? I think it is
clear that it would, in this respect, be an improvement on the existing
system. Representative government cannot but be improved by any method
which brings the representatives into closer touch with the interests
concerned in their legislation; and this advantage probably would be
secured by handing over questions of production to the Guild Congress. But
if, in spite of the safeguards proposed by the Guild Socialists, the Guild
Congress became all-powerful in such questions, if resistance to its will
by a Guild which felt ill-used became practically hopeless, I fear that
the evils now connected with the omnipotence of the State would soon
reappear. Trade Union officials, as soon as they become part of the
governing forces in the country, tend to become autocratic and
conservative; they lose touch with their constituents and gravitate, by a
psychological sympathy, into co-operation with the powers that be. Their
formal installation in authority through the Guilds Congress would
accelerate this process. They would soon tend to combine, in effect if not
obviously, with those who wield authority in Parliament. Apart from
occasional conflicts, comparable to the rivalry of opposing financiers
which now sometimes disturbs the harmony of the capitalist world, there
would, at most times, be agreement between the dominant personalities in
the two Houses. And such harmony would filch away from the individual the
liberty which he had hoped to secure by the quarrels of his masters.</p>
<p>There is no method, if we are not mistaken, by which a body representing
the whole community, whether as producers or consumers or both, can alone
be a sufficient guardian of individual liberty. The only way of preserving
sufficient liberty (and even this will be inadequate in the case of very
small minorities) is the organization of citizens with special interests
into groups, determined to preserve autonomy as regards their internal
affairs, willing to resist interference by a strike if necessary, and
sufficiently powerful (either in themselves or through their power of
appealing to public sympathy) to be able to resist the organized forces of
government successfully when their cause is such as many men think just.
If this method is to be successful we must have not only suitable
organizations but also a diffused respect for liberty, and an absence of
submissiveness to government both in theory and practice. Some risk of
disorder there must be in such a society, but this risk is as nothing
compared to the danger of stagnation which is inseparable from an
all-powerful central authority.</p>
<p>We may now sum up our discussion of the powers of Government.</p>
<p>The State, in spite of what Anarchists urge, seems a necessary institution
for certain purposes. Peace and war, tariffs, regulation of sanitary
conditions and of the sale of noxious drugs, the preservation of a just
system of distribution: these, among others, are functions which could
hardly be performed in a community in which there was no central
government. Take, for example, the liquor traffic, or the opium traffic in
China. If alcohol could be obtained at cost price without taxation, still
more if it could be obtained for nothing, as Anarchists presumably desire,
can we believe that there would not be a great and disastrous increase of
drunkenness? China was brought to the verge of ruin by opium, and every
patriotic Chinaman desired to see the traffic in opium restricted. In such
matters freedom is not a panacea, and some degree of legal restriction
seems imperative for the national health.</p>
<p>But granting that the State, in some form, must continue, we must also
grant, I think, that its powers ought to be very strictly limited to what
is absolutely necessary. There is no way of limiting its powers except by
means of groups which are jealous of their privileges and determined to
preserve their autonomy, even if this should involve resistance to laws
decreed by the State, when these laws interfere in the internal affairs of
a group in ways not warranted by the public interest. The glorification of
the State, and the doctrine that it is every citizen's duty to serve the
State, are radically against progress and against liberty. The State,
though at present a source of much evil, is also a means to certain good
things, and will be needed so long as violent and destructive impulses
remain common. But it is MERELY a means, and a means which needs to be
very carefully and sparingly used if it is not to do more harm than good.
It is not the State, but the community, the worldwide community of all
human beings present and future, that we ought to serve. And a good
community does not spring from the glory of the State, but from the
unfettered development of individuals: from happiness in daily life, from
congenial work giving opportunity for whatever constructiveness each man
or woman may possess, from free personal relations embodying love and
taking away the roots of envy in thwarted capacity from affection, and
above all from the joy of life and its expression in the spontaneous
creations of art and science. It is these things that make an age or a
nation worthy of existence, and these things are not to be secured by
bowing down before the State. It is the individual in whom all that is
good must be realized, and the free growth of the individual must be the
supreme end of a political system which is to re-fashion the world.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0006" id="link2HCH0006"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER VI — INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS </h2>
<p>THE main objects which should be served by international relations may be
taken to be two: First, the avoidance of wars, and, second, the prevention
of the oppression of weak nations by strong ones. These two objects do not
by any means necessarily lead in the same direction, since one of the
easiest ways of securing the world's peace would be by a combination of
the most powerful States for the exploitation and oppression of the
remainder. This method, however, is not one which the lover of liberty can
favor. We must keep account of both aims and not be content with either
alone.</p>
<p>One of the commonplaces of both Socialism and Anarchism is that all modern
wars are due to capitalism, and would cease if capitalism were abolished.
This view, to my mind, is only a half-truth; the half that is true is
important, but the half that is untrue is perhaps equally important when a
fundamental reconstruction of society is being considered.</p>
<p>Socialist and Anarchist critics of existing society point, with perfect
truth, to certain capitalistic factors which promote war. The first of
these is the desire of finance to find new fields of investment in
undeveloped countries. Mr. J. A. Hobson, an author who is by no means
extreme in his views, has well stated this point in his book on "The
Evolution of Modern Capitalism."<SPAN href="#linknote-55"
name="linknoteref-55" id="linknoteref-55"><small>55</small></SPAN> He says:</p>
<p>The economic tap-root, the chief directing motive of all the modern
imperialistic expansion, is the pressure of capitalist industries for
markets, primarily markets for investment, secondarily markets for surplus
products of home industry. Where the concentration of capital has gone
furthest, and where a rigorous protective system prevails, this pressure
is necessarily strongest. Not merely do the trusts and other manufacturing
trades that restrict their output for the home market more urgently
require foreign markets, but they are also more anxious to secure
protected markets, and this can only be achieved by extending the area of
political rule. This is the essential significance of the recent change in
American foreign policy as illustrated by the Spanish War, the Philippine
annexation, the Panama policy, and the new application of the Monroe
doctrine to the South American States. South America is needed as a
preferential market for investment of trust "profits" and surplus trust
products: if in time these states can be brought within a Zollverein under
the suzerainty of the United States, the financial area of operations
receives a notable accession. China as a field of railway enterprise and
general industrial development already begins to loom large in the eyes of
foresighted American business men; the growing trade in American cotton
and other goods in that country will be a subordinate consideration to the
expansion of the area for American investments. Diplomatic pressure, armed
force, and, where desirable, seizure of territory for political control,
will be engineered by the financial magnates who control the political
destiny of America. The strong and expensive American navy now beginning
to be built incidentally serves the purpose of affording profitable
contracts to the shipbuilding and metal industries: its real meaning and
use is to forward the aggressive political policy imposed upon the nation
by the economic needs of the financial capitalists.</p>
<p>It should be clearly understood that this constant pressure to extend the
area of markets is not a necessary implication of all forms of organized
industry. If competition was displaced by combinations of a genuinely
cooperative character in which the whole gain of improved economies
passed, either to the workers in wages, or to large bodies of investors in
dividends, the expansion of demand in the home markets would be so great
as to give full employment to the productive powers of concentrated
capital, and there would be no self-accumulating masses of profit
expressing themselves in new credit and demanding external employment. It
is the "monopoly" profits of trusts and combines, taken either in
construction, financial operation, or industrial working, that form a
gathering fund of self-accumulating credit whose possession by the
financial class implies a contracted demand for commodities and a
correspondingly restricted employment for capital in American industries.
Within certain limits relief can be found by stimulation of the export
trade under cover of a high protective tariff which forbids all
interference with monopoly of the home markets. But it is extremely
difficult for trusts adapted to the requirements of a profitable tied
market at home to adjust their methods of free competition in the world
markets upon a profitable basis of steady trading. Moreover, such a mode
of expansion is only appropriate to certain manufacturing trusts: the
owners of railroad, financial and other trusts must look always more to
foreign investments for their surplus profits. This ever-growing need for
fresh fields of investment for their profits is the great crux of the
financial system, and threatens to dominate the future economics and the
politics of the great Republic.</p>
<p>The financial economy of American capitalism exhibits in more dramatic
shape a tendency common to the finance of all developed industrial
nations. The large, easy flow of capital from Great Britain, Germany,
Austria, France, etc., into South African or Australian mines, into
Egyptian bonds, or the precarious securities of South American republics,
attests the same general pressure which increases with every development
of financial machinery and the more profitable control of that machinery
by the class of professional financiers</p>
<p>The kind of way in which such conditions tend toward war might have been
illustrated, if Mr. Hobson had been writing at a later date, by various
more recent cases. A higher rate of interest is obtainable on enterprises
in an undeveloped country than in a developed one, provided the risks
connected with an unsettled government can be minimized. To minimize these
risks the financiers call in the assistance of the military and naval
forces of the country which they are momentarily asserting to be theirs.
In order to have the support of public opinion in this demand they have
recourse to the power of the Press.</p>
<p>The Press is the second great factor to which critics of capitalism point
when they wish to prove that capitalism is the source of modern war. Since
the running of a big newspaper requires a large capital, the proprietors
of important organs necessarily belong to the capitalist class, and it
will be a rare and exceptional event if they do not sympathize with their
own class in opinion and outlook. They are able to decide what news the
great mass of newspaper readers shall be allowed to have. They can
actually falsify the news, or, without going so far as that, they can
carefully select it, giving such items as will stimulate the passions
which they desire to stimulate, and suppressing such items as would
provide the antidote. In this way the picture of the world in the mind of
the average newspaper reader is made to be not a true picture, but in the
main that which suits the interests of capitalists. This is true in many
directions, but above all in what con- cerns the relations between
nations. The mass of the population of a country can be led to love or
hate any other country at the will of the newspaper proprietors, which is
often, directly or indirectly, influenced by the will of the great
financiers. So long as enmity between England and Russia was desired, our
newspapers were full of the cruel treatment meted out to Russian political
prisoners, the oppression of Finland and Russian Poland, and other such
topics. As soon as our foreign policy changed, these items disappeared
from the more important newspapers, and we heard instead of the misdeeds
of Germany. Most men are not sufficiently critical to be on their guard
against such influences, and until they are, the power of the Press will
remain.</p>
<p>Besides these two influences of capitalism in promoting war, there is
another, much less emphasized by the critics of capitalism, but by no
means less important: I mean the pugnacity which tends to be developed in
men who have the habit of command. So long as capitalist society persists,
an undue measure of power will be in the hands of those who have acquired
wealth and influence through a great position in industry or finance. Such
men are in the habit, in private life, of finding their will seldom
questioned; they are surrounded by obsequious satellites and are not
infrequently engaged in conflicts with Trade Unions. Among their friends
and acquaintances are included those who hold high positions in government
or administration, and these men equally are liable to become autocratic
through the habit of giving orders. It used to be customary to speak of
the "governing classes," but nominal democracy has caused this phrase to
go out of fashion. Nevertheless, it still retains much truth; there are
still in any capitalist community those who command and those who as a
rule obey. The outlook of these two classes is very different, though in a
modern society there is a continuous gradation from the extreme of the one
to the extreme of the other. The man who is accustomed to find submission
to his will becomes indignant on the occasions when he finds opposition.
Instinctively he is convinced that opposition is wicked and must be
crushed. He is therefore much more willing than the average citizen to
resort to war against his rivals. Accordingly we find, though, of course,
with very notable exceptions, that in the main those who have most power
are most warlike, and those who have least power are least disposed to
hatred of foreign nations. This is one of the evils inseparable from the
concentration of power. It will only be cured by the abolition of
capitalism if the new system is one which allows very much less power to
single individuals. It will not be cured by a system which substitutes the
power of Ministers or officials for the power of capitalists This is one
reason, additional to those mentioned in the preceding chapter, for
desiring to see a diminution in the authority of the State.</p>
<p>Not only does the concentration of power tend to cause wars, but, equally,
wars and the fear of them bring about the necessity for the concentration
of power. So long as the community is exposed to sudden dangers, the
possibility of quick decision is absolutely necessary to
self-preservation. The cumbrous machinery of deliberative decisions by the
people is impossible in a crisis, and therefore so long as crises are
likely to occur, it is impossible to abolish the almost autocratic power
of governments. In this case, as in most others, each of two correlative
evils tends to perpetuate the other. The existence of men with the habit
of power increases the risk of war, and the risk of war makes it
impossible to establish a system where no man possesses great power.</p>
<p>So far we have been considering what is true in the contention that
capitalism causes modern wars. It is time now to look at the other side,
and to ask ourselves whether the abolition of capitalism would, by itself,
be sufficient to prevent war.</p>
<p>I do not myself believe that this is the case. The outlook of both
Socialists and Anarchists seems to me, in this respect as in some others,
to be unduly divorced from the fundamental instincts of human nature.
There were wars before there was capital- ism, and fighting is habitual
among animals. The power of the Press in promoting war is entirely due to
the fact that it is able to appeal to certain instincts. Man is naturally
competitive, acquisitive, and, in a greater or less degree, pugnacious.
When the Press tells him that so-and-so is his enemy, a whole set of
instincts in him responds to the suggestion. It is natural to most men to
suppose that they have enemies and to find a certain fulfillment of their
nature when they embark upon a contest. What a man believes upon grossly
insufficient evidence is an index to his desires—desires of which he
himself is often unconscious. If a man is offered a fact which goes
against his instincts, he will scrutinize it closely, and unless the
evidence is overwhelming, he will refuse to believe it. If, on the other
hand, he is offered something which affords a reason for acting in
accordance with his instincts, he will accept it even on the slenderest
evidence. The origin of myths is explained in this way, and much of what
is currently believed in international affairs is no better than myth.
Although capitalism affords in modern society the channel by which the
instinct of pugnacity finds its outlet, there is reason to fear that, if
this channel were closed, some other would be found, unless education and
environment were so changed as enormously to diminish the strength of the
competitive instinct. If an economic reorganization can effect this it may
pro- vide a real safeguard against war, but if not, it is to be feared
that the hopes of universal peace will prove delusive.</p>
<p>The abolition of capitalism might, and very likely would, greatly diminish
the incentives to war which are derived from the Press and from the desire
of finance to find new fields for investment in undeveloped countries, but
those which are derived from the instinct of command and the impatience of
opposition might remain, though perhaps in a less virulent form than at
present. A democracy which has power is almost always more bellicose than
one which is excluded from its due share in the government. The
internationalism of Marx is based upon the assumption that the proletariat
everywhere are oppressed by the ruling classes. The last words of the
Communist Manifesto embody this idea—</p>
<p>Let the ruling classes tremble at a Communistic revolution. The
proletarians have nothing to lose but their chains. They have a world to
win. Working men of all countries, unite!</p>
<p>So long as the proletarians have nothing to lose but their chains, it is
not likely that their enmity will be directed against other proletarians.
If the world had developed as Marx expected, the kind of internationalism
which he foresaw might have inspired a universal social revolution.
Russia, which devel- oped more nearly than any other country upon the
lines of his system, has had a revolution of the kind which he expected.
If the development in other countries had been similar, it is highly
probable that this revolution would have spread throughout the civilized
world. The proletariat of all countries might have united against the
capitalists as their common enemy, and in the bond of an identical hatred
they might for the moment have been free from hatred toward each other.
Even then, this ground of union would have ceased with their victory, and
on the morrow of the social revolution the old national rivalries might
have revived. There is no alchemy by which a universal harmony can be
produced out of hatred. Those who have been inspired to action by the
doctrine of the class war will have acquired the habit of hatred, and will
instinctively seek new enemies when the old ones have been vanquished.</p>
<p>But in actual fact the psychology of the working man in any of the Western
democracies is totally unlike that which is assumed in the Communist
Manifesto. He does not by any means feel that he has nothing to lose but
his chains, nor indeed is this true. The chains which bind Asia and Africa
in subjection to Europe are partly riveted by him. He is himself part of a
great system of tyranny and exploitation. Universal freedom would remove,
not only his own chains, which are comparatively light, but the far
heavier chains which he has helped to fasten upon the subject races of the
world.</p>
<p>Not only do the working men of a country like England have a share in the
benefit accruing from the exploitation of inferior races, but many among
them also have their part in the capitalist system. The funds of Trade
Unions and Friendly Societies are invested in ordinary undertakings, such
as railways; many of the better-paid wage-earners have put their savings
into government securities; and almost all who are politically active feel
themselves part of the forces that determine public policy, through the
power of the Labor Party and the greater unions. Owing to these causes
their outlook on life has become to a considerable extent impregnated with
capitalism and as their sense of power has grown, their nationalism has
increased. This must continue to be true of any internationalism which is
based upon hatred of the capitalist and adherence to the doctrine of the
class war. Something more positive and constructive than this is needed if
governing democracies are not to inherit the vices of governing classes in
the past.</p>
<p>I do not wish to be thought to deny that capitalism does very much to
promote wars, or that wars would probably be less frequent and less
destructive if private property were abolished. On the contrary, I believe
that the abolition of private ownership of land and capital is a necessary
step toward any world in which the nations are to live at peace with one
another. I am only arguing that this step, necessary as it is, will not
alone suffice for this end, but that among the causes of war there are
others that go deeper into the roots of human nature than any that
orthodox Socialists are wont to acknowledge.</p>
<p>Let us take an instance. In Australia and California there is an intense
dislike and fear toward the yellow races. The causes of this are complex;
the chief among them are two, labor competition and instinctive
race-hatred. It is probable that, if race- hatred did not exist, the
difficulties of labor competition could be overcome. European immigrants
also compete, but they are not excluded. In a sparsely populated country,
industrious cheap labor could, with a little care, be so utilized as to
enrich the existing inhabitants; it might, for example, be confined to
certain kinds of work, by custom if not by law. But race-hatred opens
men's minds to the evils of competition and closes them against the
advantages of co-operation; it makes them regard with horror the somewhat
unfamiliar vices of the aliens, while our own vices are viewed with mild
toleration. I cannot but think that, if Australia were completely
socialized, there would still remain the same popular objection as at
present to any large influx of Chinese or Japanese labor. Yet if Japan
also were to become a Socialist State, the Japanese might well continue to
feel the pressure of population and the desire for an outlet. In such
circumstances, all the passions and interests required to produce a war
would exist, in spite of the establishment of Socialism in both countries.
Ants are as completely Socialistic as any community can possibly be, yet
they put to death any ant which strays among them by mistake from a
neighboring ant-heap. Men do not differ much from ants, as regards their
instincts in this respect, where- ever there is a great divergence of
race, as between white men and yellow men. Of course the instinct of
race-hostility can be overcome by suitable circumstances; but in the
absence of such circumstances it remains a formidable menace to the
world's peace.</p>
<p>If the peace of the world is ever to become secure, I believe there will
have to be, along with other changes, a development of the idea which
inspires the project of a League of Nations. As time goes on, the
destructiveness of war grows greater and its profits grow less: the
rational argument against war acquires more and more force as the
increasing productivity of labor makes it possible to devote a greater and
greater proportion of the population to the work of mutual slaughter. In
quiet times, or when a great war has just ended, men's moods are amenable
to the rational grounds in favor of peace, and it is possible to
inaugurate schemes designed to make wars less frequent. Probably no
civilized nation would embark upon an aggressive war if it were fairly
certain in advance that the aggressor must be defeated. This could be
achieved if most great nations came to regard the peace of the world as of
such importance that they would side against an aggressor even in a
quarrel in which they had no direct interest. It is on this hope that the
League of Nations is based.</p>
<p>But the League of Nations, like the abolition of private property, will be
by no means sufficient if it is not accompanied or quickly followed by
other reforms. It is clear that such reforms, if they are to be effective,
must be international; the world must move as a whole in these matters, if
it is to move at all. One of the most obvious necessities, if peace is to
be secure, is a measure of disarmament. So long as the present vast armies
and navies exist, no system can prevent the risk of war. But disarmament,
if it is to serve its purpose, must be simultaneous and by mutual
agreement among all the Great Powers. And it is not likely to be
successful so long as hatred and suspicion rule between nations, for each
nation will suspect its neighbor of not carrying out the bargain fairly. A
different mental and moral atmosphere from that to which we are accustomed
in international affairs will be necessary if agreements between nations
are to succeed in averting catastrophes. If once such an atmosphere
existed it might be perpetuated and strengthened by wise institutions; but
it cannot be CREATED by institutions alone. International co-operation
requires mutual good will, and good will, however it has arisen, is only
to be PRESERVED by co-operation. The international future depends upon the
possibility of the initial creation of good will between nations.</p>
<p>It is in this sort of matter that revolutions are most useful. If the
Russian Revolution had been accompanied by a revolution in Germany, the
dramatic suddenness of the change might have shaken Europe, for the
moment, out of its habits of thought: the idea of fraternity might have
seemed, in the twinkling of an eye, to have entered the world of practical
politics; and no idea is so practical as the idea of the brotherhood of
man, if only people can be startled into believing in it. If once the idea
of fraternity between nations were inaugurated with the faith and vigor
belonging to a new revolution, all the difficulties surrounding it would
melt away, for all of them are due to suspicion and the tyranny of ancient
prejudice. Those who (as is common in the English-speaking world) reject
revolution as a method, and praise the gradual piecemeal development which
(we are told) constitutes solid progress, overlook the effect of dramatic
events in changing the mood and the beliefs of whole populations. A
simultaneous revolution in Germany and Russia would no doubt have had such
an effect, and would have made the creation of a new world possible here
and now.</p>
<p>Dis aliter visum: the millennium is not for our time. The great moment has
passed, and for ourselves it is again the distant hope that must inspire
us, not the immediate breathless looking for the deliverance.<SPAN href="#linknote-56" name="linknoteref-56" id="linknoteref-56"><small>56</small></SPAN>
But we have seen what might have been, and we know that great
possibilities do arise in times of crisis. In some such sense as this, it
may well be true that the Socialist revolution is the road to universal
peace, and that when it has been traversed all the other conditions for
the cessation of wars will grow of themselves out of the changed mental
and moral atmosphere.</p>
<p>There is a certain class of difficulties which surrounds the sober
idealist in all speculations about the not too distant future. These are
the cases where the solution believed by most idealists to be universally
applicable is for some reason impossible, and is, at the same time,
objected to for base or interested motives by all upholders of existing
inequalities. The case of Tropical Africa will illustrate what I mean. It
would be difficult seriously to advocate the immediate introduction of
parliamentary government for the natives of this part of the world, even
if it were accompanied by women's suffrage and proportional
representation. So far as I know, no one supposes the populations of these
regions capable of self- determination, except Mr. Lloyd George. There can
be no doubt that, whatever regime may be introduced in Europe, African
negroes will for a long time to come be governed and exploited by
Europeans. If the European States became Socialistic, and refused, under a
Quixotic impulse, to enrich themselves at the expense of the defenseless
inhabitants of Africa, those inhabitants would not thereby gain; on the
contrary, they would lose, for they would be handed over to the tender
mercies of individual traders, operating with armies of reprobate bravos,
and committing every atrocity to which the civilized barbarian is prone.
The European governments cannot divest themselves of responsibility in
regard to Africa. They must govern there, and the best that can be hoped
is that they should govern with a minimum of cruelty and rapacity. From
the point of view of preserving the peace of the world, the problem is to
parcel out the advantages which white men derive from their position in
Africa in such a way that no nation shall feel a sense of injustice. This
problem is comparatively simple, and might no doubt be solved on the lines
of the war aims of the Inter-Allied Socialists. But it is not this problem
which I wish to discuss. What I wish to consider is, how could a Socialist
or an Anarchist community govern and administer an African region, full of
natural wealth, but inhabited by a quite uncivilized population? Unless
great precautions were taken the white community, under the circumstances,
would acquire the position and the instincts of a slave-owner. It would
tend to keep the negroes down to the bare level of subsistence, while
using the produce of their country to increase the comfort and splendor of
the Communist community. It would do this with that careful
unconsciousness which now characterizes all the worst acts of nations.
Administrators would be appointed and would be expected to keep silence as
to their methods. Busybodies who reported horrors would be disbelieved,
and would be said to be actuated by hatred toward the existing regime and
by a perverse love for every country but their own. No doubt, in the first
generous enthusiasm accompanying the establishment of the new regime at
home, there would be every intention of making the natives happy, but
gradually they would be forgotten, and only the tribute coming from their
country would be remembered. I do not say that all these evils are
unavoidable; I say only that they will not be avoided unless they are
foreseen and a deliberate conscious effort is made to prevent their
realization. If the white communities should ever reach the point of
wishing to carry out as far as possible the principles underlying the
revolt against capitalism, they will have to find a way of establishing an
absolute disinterestedness in their dealings with subject races. It will
be necessary to avoid the faintest suggestion of capitalistic profit in
the government of Africa, and to spend in the countries themselves
whatever they would be able to spend if they were self-governing.
Moreover, it must always be remembered that backwardness in civilization
is not necessarily incurable, and that with time even the populations of
Central Africa may become capable of democratic self-government, provided
Europeans bend their energies to this purpose.</p>
<p>The problem of Africa is, of course, a part of the wider problems of
Imperialism, but it is that part in which the application of Socialist
principles is most difficult. In regard to Asia, and more particularly in
regard to India and Persia, the application of principles is clear in
theory though difficult in political practice. The obstacles to
self-government which exist in Africa do not exist in the same measure in
Asia. What stands in the way of freedom of Asiatic populations is not
their lack of intelligence, but only their lack of military prowess, which
makes them an easy prey to our lust for dominion. This lust would probably
be in temporary abeyance on the morrow of a Socialist revolution, and at
such a moment a new departure in Asiatic policy might be taken with
permanently beneficial results. I do not mean, of course, that we should
force upon India that form of democratic government which we have
developed for our own needs. I mean rather that we should leave India to
choose its own form of government, its own manner of education and its own
type of civilization. India has an ancient tradition, very different from
that of Western Europe, a tradition highly valued by educated Hindoos, but
not loved by our schools and colleges. The Hindoo Nationalist feels that
his country has a type of culture containing elements of value that are
absent, or much less marked, in the West; he wishes to be free to preserve
this, and desires political freedom for such reasons rather than for those
that would most naturally appeal to an Englishman in the same subject
position. The belief of the European in his own Kultur tends to be
fanatical and ruthless, and for this reason, as much as for any other, the
independence of extra-European civilization is of real importance to the
world, for it is not by a dead uniformity that the world as a whole is
most enriched.</p>
<p>I have set forth strongly all the major difficulties in the way of the
preservation of the world's peace, not because I believe these
difficulties to be insuperable, but, on the contrary, because I believe
that they can be overcome if they are recognized. A correct diagnosis is
necessarily the first step toward a cure. The existing evils in
international relations spring, at bottom, from psychological causes, from
motives forming part of human nature as it is at present. Among these the
chief are competitiveness, love of power, and envy, using envy in that
broad sense in which it includes the instinctive dislike of any gain to
others not accompanied by an at least equal gain to ourselves. The evils
arising from these three causes can be removed by a better education and a
better economic and political system.</p>
<p>Competitiveness is by no means wholly an evil. When it takes the form of
emulation in the service of the public, or in discovery or the production
of works of art, it may become a very useful stimulus, urging men to
profitable effort beyond what they would otherwise make. It is only
harmful when it aims at the acquisition of goods which are limited in
amount, so that what one man possesses he holds at the expense of another.
When competitiveness takes this form it is necessarily attended by fear,
and out of fear cruelty is almost inevitably developed. But a social
system providing for a more just distribution of material goods might
close to the instinct of competitiveness those channels in which it is
harmful, and cause it to flow instead in channels in which it would become
a benefit to mankind. This is one great reason why the communal ownership
of land and capital would be likely to have a beneficial effect upon human
nature, for human nature, as it exists in adult men and women, is by no
means a fixed datum, but a product of circumstances, education and
opportunity operating upon a highly malleable native disposition.</p>
<p>What is true of competitiveness is equally true of love of power. Power,
in the form in which it is now usually sought, is power of command, power
of imposing one's will upon others by force, open or concealed. This form
of power consists, in essence, in thwarting others, for it is only
displayed when others are compelled to do what they do not wish to do.
Such power, we hope, the social system which is to supersede capitalist
will reduce to a minimum by the methods which we outlined in the preceding
chapter. These methods can be applied in international no less than in
national affairs. In international affairs the same formula of federalism
will apply: self- determination for every group in regard to matters which
concern it much more vitally than they concern others, and government by a
neutral authority embracing rival groups in all matters in which
conflicting interests of groups come into play; lout always with the fixed
principle that the functions of government are to be reduced to the bare
minimum compatible with justice and the prevention of private violence. In
such a world the present harmful outlets for the love of power would be
closed. But the power which consists in persuasion, in teaching, in
leading men to a new wisdom or the realization of new possibilities of
happiness—this kind of power, which may be wholly beneficial, would
remain untouched, and many vigorous men, who in the actual world devote
their energies to domination, would in such a world find their energies
directed to the creation of new goods rather than the perpetuation of
ancient evils.</p>
<p>Envy, the third of the psychological causes to which we attributed what is
bad in the actual world, depends in most natures upon that kind of
fundamental discontent which springs from a lack of free development, from
thwarted instinct, and from the impossibility of realizing an imagined
happiness. Envy cannot be cured by preaching; preaching, at the best, will
only alter its manifestations and lead it to adopt more subtle forms of
concealment. Except in those rare natures in which generosity dominates in
spite of circumstances, the only cure for envy is freedom and the joy of
life. From populations largely deprived of the simple instinctive
pleasures of leisure and love, sunshine and green fields, generosity of
outlook and kindliness of dispositions are hardly to be expected. In such
populations these qualities are not likely to be found, even among the
fortunate few, for these few are aware, however dimly, that they are
profiting by an injustice, and that they can only continue to enjoy their
good fortune by deliberately ignoring those with whom it is not shared. If
generosity and kindliness are to be common, there must be more care than
there is at present for the elementary wants of human nature, and more
realization that the diffusion of happiness among all who are not the
victims of some peculiar misfortune is both possible and imperative. A
world full of happiness would not wish to plunge into war, and would not
be filled with that grudging hostility which our cramped and narrow
existence forces upon average human nature. A world full of happiness is
not beyond human power to create; the obstacles imposed by inanimate
nature are not insuperable. The real obstacles lie in the heart of man,
and the cure for these is a firm hope, informed and fortified by thought.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0007" id="link2HCH0007"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER VII — SCIENCE AND ART UNDER SOCIALISM </h2>
<p>SOCIALISM has been advocated by most of its champions chiefly as a means
of increasing the welfare of the wage earning classes, and more
particularly their material welfare. It has seemed accordingly, to some
men whose aims are not material, as if it has nothing to offer toward the
general advancement of civilization in the way of art and thought. Some of
its advocates, moreover—and among these Marx must be included—have
written, no doubt not deliberately, as if with the Socialist revolution
the millennium would have arrived, and there would be no need of further
progress for the human race. I do not know whether our age is more
restless than that which preceded it, or whether it has merely become more
impregnated with the idea of evolution, but, for whatever reason, we have
grown incapable of believing in a state of static perfection, and we
demand, of any social system, which is to have our approval, that it shall
contain within itself a stimulus and opportunity for progress toward
something still better. The doubts thus raised by Socialist writers make
it necessary to inquire whether Socialism would in fact be hostile to art
and science, and whether it would be likely to produce a stereotyped
society in which progress would become difficult and slow.</p>
<p>It is not enough that men and women should be made comfortable in a
material sense. Many members of the well-to-do classes at present, in
spite of opportunity, contribute nothing of value to the life of the
world, and do not even succeed in securing for themselves any personal
happiness worthy to be so called. The multiplication of such individuals
would be an achievement of the very minutest value; and if Socialism were
merely to bestow upon all the kind of life and outlook which is now
enjoyed by the more apathetic among the well-to-do, it would offer little
that could inspire enthusiasm in any generous spirit.</p>
<p>"The true role of collective existence," says M. Naquet,<SPAN href="#linknote-57" name="linknoteref-57" id="linknoteref-57"><small>57</small></SPAN>"
. . . is to learn, to discover, to know. Eating, drinking, sleeping,
living, in a word, is a mere accessory. In this respect, we are not
distinguished from the brute. Knowledge is the goal. If I were condemned
to choose between a humanity materially happy, glutted after the manner of
a flock of sheep in a field, and a humanity existing in misery, but from
which emanated, here and there, some eternal truth, it is on the latter
that my choice would fall."</p>
<p>This statement puts the alternative in a very extreme form in which it is
somewhat unreal. It may be said in reply that for those who have had the
leisure and the opportunity to enjoy "eternal truths" it is easy to exalt
their importance at the expense of sufferings which fall on others. This
is true; but, if it is taken as disposing of the question, it leaves out
of account the importance of thought for progress. Viewing the life of
mankind as a whole, in the future as well as in the present, there can be
no question that a society in which some men pursue knowledge while others
endure great poverty offers more hope of ultimate good than a society in
which all are sunk in slothful comfort. It is true that poverty is a great
evil, but it is not true that material prosperity is in itself a great
good. If it is to have any real value to society, it must be made a means
to the advancement of those higher goods that belong to the life of the
mind. But the life of the mind does not consist of thought and knowledge
alone, nor can it be completely healthy unless it has some instinctive
contact, however deeply buried, with the general life of the community.
Divorced from the social instinct, thought, like art, tends to become
finicky and precious. It is the position of such art and thought as is
imbued with the instinctive sense of service to mankind that we wish to
consider, for it is this alone that makes up the life of the mind in the
sense in which it is a vital part of the life of the community. Will the
life of the mind in this sense be helped or hindered by Socialism? And
will there still be a sufficient spur to progress to prevent a condition
of Byzantine immobility?</p>
<p>In considering this question we are, in a certain sense, passing outside
the atmosphere of democracy. The general good of the community is realized
only in individuals, but it is realized much more fully in some
individuals than in others. Some men have a comprehensive and penetrating
intellect, enabling them to appreciate and remember what has been thought
and known by their predecessors, and to discover new regions in which they
enjoy all the high delights of the mental explorer. Others have the power
of creating beauty, giving bodily form to impalpable visions out of which
joy comes to many. Such men are more fortunate than the mass, and also
more important for the collective life. A larger share of the general sum
of good is concentrated in them than in the ordinary man and woman; but
also their contribution to the general good is greater. They stand out
among men and cannot be wholly fitted into the framework of democratic
equality. A social system which would render them unproductive would stand
condemned, whatever other merits it might have.</p>
<p>The first thing to realize—though it is difficult in a commercial
age—is that what is best in creative mental activity cannot be
produced by any system of monetary rewards. Opportunity and the stimulus
of an invigorating spiritual atmosphere are important, but, if they are
presented, no financial inducements will be required, while if they are
absent, material compensations will be of no avail. Recognition, even if
it takes the form of money, can bring a certain pleasure in old age to the
man of science who has battled all his life against academic prejudice, or
to the artist who has endured years of ridicule for not painting in the
manner of his predecessors; but it is not by the remote hope of such
pleasures that their work has been inspired. All the most important work
springs from an uncalculating impulse, and is best promoted, not by
rewards after the event, but by circumstances which keep the impulse alive
and afford scope for the activities which it inspires. In the creation of
such circumstances our present system is much at fault. Will Socialism be
better?</p>
<p>I do not think this question can be answered without specifying the kind
of Socialism that is intended: some forms of Socialism would, I believe,
be even more destructive in this respect than the present capitalist
regime, while others would be immeasurably better. Three things which a
social system can provide or withhold are helpful to mental creation:
first, technical training; second, liberty to follow the creative impulse;
third, at least the possibility of ultimate appreciation by some public,
whether large or small. We may leave out of our discussion both individual
genius and those intangible conditions which make some ages great and
others sterile in art and science—not because these are unimportant,
but because they are too little understood to be taken account of in
economic or political organization. The three conditions we have mentioned
seem to cover most of what can be SEEN to be useful or harmful from our
present point of view, and it is therefore to them that we shall confine
ourselves.</p>
<p>1. Technical Training.—Technical training at present, whether in
science or art, requires one or other of two conditions. Either a boy must
be the son of well-to-do parents who can afford to keep him while he
acquires his education, or he must show so much ability at an early age as
to enable him to subsist on scholarships until he is ready to earn his
living. The former condition is, of course, a mere matter of luck, and
could not be preserved in its present form under any kind of Socialism or
Communism. This loss is emphasized by defenders of the present system, and
no doubt it would be, to same extent, a real loss. But the well-to-do are
a small proportion of the population, and presumably on the average no
more talented by nature than their less fortunate contemporaries. If the
advantages which are enjoyed now by those few among them who are capable
of good work in science or art could be extended, even in a slightly
attenuated form, to all who are similarly gifted, the result would almost
infallibly be a gain, and much ability which is now wasted would be
rendered fruitful. But how is this to be effected?</p>
<p>The system of scholarships obtained by competition, though better than
nothing, is objectionable from many points of view. It introduces the
competitive spirit into the work of the very young; it makes them regard
knowledge from the standpoint of what is useful in examinations rather
than in the light of its intrinsic interest or importance; it places a
premium upon that sort of ability which is displayed precociously in glib
answers to set questions rather than upon the kind that broods on
difficulties and remains for a time rather dumb. What is perhaps worse
than any of these defects is the tendency to cause overwork in youth,
leading to lack of vigor and interest when manhood has been reached. It
can hardly be doubted that by this cause, at present, many fine minds have
their edge blunted and their keenness destroyed.</p>
<p>State Socialism might easily universalize the system of scholarships
obtained by competitive examination, and if it did so it is to he feared
that it would be very harmful. State Socialists at present tend to be
enamored of the systems which is exactly of the kind that every bureaucrat
loves: orderly, neat, giving a stimulus to industrious habits, and
involving no waste of a sort that could be tabulated in statistics or
accounts of public expenditure. Such men will argue that free higher
education is expensive to the community, and only useful in the case of
those who have exceptional abilities; it ought, therefore, they will say,
not to be given to all, but only to those who will become more useful
members of society through receiving it. Such arguments make a great
appeal to what are called "practical" men, and the answers to them are of
a sort which it is difficult to render widely convincing. Revolt against
the evils of competition is, however, part of the very essence of the
Socialist's protest against the existing order, and on this ground, if on
no other, those who favor Socialism may be summoned to look for some
better solution.</p>
<p>Much the simplest solution, and the only really effective one, is to make
every kind of education free up to the age of twenty-one for all boys and
girls who desire it. The majority will be tired of education before that
age, and will prefer to begin other work sooner; this will lead to a
natural selection of those with strong interests in some pursuit requiring
a long training. Among those selected in this way by their own
inclinations, probably almost all tho have marked abilities of the kind in
question will be included. It is true that there will also be many who
have very little ability; the desire to become a painter, for example, is
by no means confined to those who can paint. But this degree of waste
could well be borne by the community; it would be immeasurably less than
that now entailed by the support of the idle rich. Any system which aims
at avoiding this kind of waste must entail the far more serious waste of
rejecting or spoiling some of the best ability in each generation. The
system of free education up to any grade for all who desire it is the only
system which is consistent with the principles of liberty, and the only
one which gives a reasonable hope of affording full scope for talent. This
system is equally compatible with all forms of Socialism and Anarchism.
Theoretically, it is compatible with capitalism, but practically it is so
opposite in spirit that it would hardly be feasible without a complete
economic reconstruction. The fact that Socialism would facilitate it must
be reckoned a very powerful argument in favor of change, for the waste of
talent at present in the poorer classes of society must be stupendous.</p>
<p>2. Liberty to follow the creative impulse.— When a man's training
has been completed, if he is possessed of really great abilities, he will
do his best work if he is completely free to follow his bent, creating
what seems good to him, regardless of the judgment of "experts." At
present this is only possible for two classes of people: those who have
private means, and those who can earn a living by an occupation that does
not absorb their whole energies. Under Socialism, there will be no one
with private means, and if there is to be no loss as regards art and
science, the opportunity which now comes by accident to a few will have to
be provided deliberately for a much larger number. The men who have used
private means as an opportunity for creative work have been few but
important: one might mention Milton, Shelley, Keats and Darwin as
examples. Probably none of these would have produced as good work if they
had had to earn their livelihood. If Darwin had been a university teacher,
he would of course have been dismissed from his post by the influence of
the clerics on account of his scandalous theories.</p>
<p>Nevertheless, the bulk of the creative work of the world is done at
present by men who subsist by some other occupation. Science, and research
generally, are usually done in their spare time by men who live by
teaching. There is no great objection to this in the case of science,
provided the number of hours devoted to teaching is not excessive. It is
partly because science and teaching are so easily combined that science is
vigorous in the present age. In music, a composer who is also a performer
enjoys similar advantages, but one who is not a performer must starve,
unless he is rich or willing to pander to the public taste. In the fine
arts, as a rule, it is not easy in the modern world either to make a
living by really good work or to find a subsidiary profession which leaves
enough leisure for creation. This is presumably one reason, though by no
means the only one, why art is less flourishing than science.</p>
<p>The bureaucratic State Socialist will have a simple solution for these
difficulties. He will appoint a body consisting of the most eminent
celebrities in an art or a science, whose business it shall be to judge
the work of young men, and to issue licenses to those whose productions
find favor in their eyes. A licensed artist shall be considered to have
performed his duty to the community by producing works of art. But of
course he will have to prove his industry by never failing to produce in
reasonable quantities, and his continued ability by never failing to
please his eminent judges—until, in the fulness of time, he becomes
a judge himself. In this way, the authorities will insure that the artist
shall be competent, regular, and obedient to the best traditions of his
art. Those who fail to fulfil these conditions will be compelled by the
withdrawal of their license to seek some less dubious mode of earning
their living. Such will be the ideal of the State Socialist.</p>
<p>In such a world all that makes life tolerable to the lover of beauty would
perish. Art springs from a wild and anarchic side of human nature; between
the artist and the bureaucrat there must always be a profound mutual
antagonism, an age-long battle in which the artist, always outwardly
worsted, wins in the end through the gratitude of mankind for the joy that
he puts into their lives. If the wild side of human nature is to be
permanently subjected to the orderly rules of the benevolent,
uncomprehending bureaucrat, the joy of life will perish out of the earth,
and the very impulse to live will gradually wither and die. Better a
thousandfold the present world with all its horrors than such a dead mummy
of a world. Better Anarchism, with all its risks, than a State Socialism
that subjects to rule what must be spontaneous and free if it is to have
any value. It is this nightmare that makes artists, and lovers of beauty
generally, so often suspicious of Socialism. But there is nothing in the
essence of Socialism to make art impossible: only certain forms of
Socialism would entail this danger. William Morris was a Socialist, and
was a Socialist very largely because he was an artist. And in this he was
not irrational.</p>
<p>It is impossible for art, or any of the higher creative activities, to
flourish under any system which requires that the artist shall prove his
competence to some body of authorities before he is allowed to follow his
impulse. Any really great artist is almost sure to be thought incompetent
by those among his seniors who would be generally regarded as best
qualified to form an opinion. And the mere fact of having to produce work
which will please older men is hostile to a free spirit and to bold
innovation. Apart from this difficulty, selection by older men would lead
to jealousy and intrigue and back-biting, producing a poisonous atmosphere
of underground competition. The only effect of such a plan would be to
eliminate the few who now slip through owing to some fortunate accident.
It is not by any system, but by freedom alone, that art can flourish.</p>
<p>There are two ways by which the artist could secure freedom under
Socialism of the right kind. He might undertake regular work outside his
art, doing only a few hours' work a day and receiving proportionately less
pay than those who do a full day's work. He ought, in that case, to be at
liberty to sell his pictures if he could find purchasers. Such a system
would have many advantages. It would leave absolutely every man free to
become an artist, provided he were willing to suffer a certain economic
loss. This would not deter those in whom the impulse was strong and
genuine, but would tend to exclude the dilettante. Many young artists at
present endure voluntarily much greater poverty than need be entailed by
only doing half the usual day's work in a well-organized Socialist
community; and some degree of hardship is not objectionable, as a test of
the strength of the creative impulse, and as an offset to the peculiar
joys of the creative life.</p>
<p>The other possibility<SPAN href="#linknote-58" name="linknoteref-58" id="linknoteref-58"><small>58</small></SPAN> would be that the necessaries of
life should be free, as Anarchists desire, to all equally, regardless of
whether they work or not. Under this plan, every man could live without
work: there would be what might be called a "vagabond's wage," sufficient
for existence but not for luxury. The artist who preferred to have his
whole time for art and enjoyment might live on the "vagabond's wage"—traveling
on foot when the humor seized him to see foreign countries, enjoying the
air and the sun, as free as the birds, and perhaps scarcely less happy.
Such men would bring color and diversity into the life of the community;
their outlook would be different from that of steady, stay-at-home
workers, and would keep alive a much-needed element of light- heartedness
which our sober, serious civilization tends to kill. If they became very
numerous, they might be too great an economic burden on the workers; but I
doubt if there are many with enough capacity for simple enjoyments to
choose poverty and free- dom in preference to the comparatively light and
pleasant work which will be usual in those days.</p>
<p>By either of these methods, freedom can be preserved for the artist in a
socialistic commonwealth— far more complete freedom, and far more
widespread, than any that now exists except for the possessors of capital.</p>
<p>But there still remain some not altogether easy problems. Take, for
example, the publishing of books. There will not, under Socialism, be
private publishers as at present: under State Socialism, presumably the
State will be the sole publisher, while under Syndicalism or Guild
Socialism the Federation du Livre will have the whole of the trade in its
hands. Under these circumstances, who is to decide what MSS. are to be
printed? It is clear that opportunities exist for an Index more rigorous
than that of the Inquisition. If the State were the sole publisher, it
would doubtless refuse books opposed to State Socialism. If the Federation
du Livre were the ultimate arbiter, what publicity could be obtained for
works criticising it? And apart from such political difficulties we should
have, as regards literature, that very censorship by eminent officials
which we agreed to regard as disastrous when we were considering the fine
arts in general. The difficulty is serious, and a way of meeting it must
be found if literature is to remain free.</p>
<p>Kropotkin, who believes that manual and intellectual work should be
combined, holds that authors themselves should be compositors,
bookbinders, etc. He even seems to suggest that the whole of the manual
work involved in producing books should be done by authors. It may be
doubted whether there are enough authors in the world for this to be
possible, and in any case I cannot but think that it would be a waste of
time for them to leave the work they understand in order to do badly work
which others could do far better and more quickly. That, however, does not
touch our present point, which is the question how the MSS. to be printed
will be selected. In Kropotkin's plan there will presumably be an Author's
Guild, with a Committee of Management, if Anarchism allows such things.
This Committee of Management will decide which of the books submitted to
it are worthy to be printed. Among these will be included those by the
Committee and their friends, but not those by their enemies. Authors of
rejected MSS. will hardly have the patience to spend their time setting up
the works of successful rivals, and there will have to be an elaborate
system of log-rolling if any books are to be printed at all. It hardly
looks as if this plan would conduce to harmony among literary men, or
would lead to the publication of any book of an unconventional tendency.
Kropotkin's own books, for example, would hardly have found favor.</p>
<p>The only way of meeting these difficulties, whether under State Socialism
or Guild Socialism or Anarchism, seems to be by making it possible for an
author to pay for the publication of his book if it is not such as the
State or the Guild is willing to print at its own expense. I am aware that
this method is contrary to the spirit of Socialism, but I do not see what
other way there is of securing freedom. The payment might be made by
undertaking to engage for an assigned period in some work of recognized
utility and to hand over such proportion of the earnings as might be
necessary. The work undertaken might of course be, as Kropotkin suggests,
the manual part of the production of books, but I see no special reason
why it should be. It would have to be an absolute rule that no book should
be refused, no matter what the nature of its contents might be, if payment
for publication were offered at the standard rate. An author who had
admirers would be able to secure their help in payment. An unknown author
might, it is true, have to suffer a considerable loss of comfort in order
to make his payment, but that would give an automatic means of eliminating
those whose writing was not the result of any very profound impulse and
would be by no means wholly an evil.</p>
<p>Probably some similar method would be desirable as regards the publishing
and performing of new music.</p>
<p>What we have been suggesting will, no doubt, be objected to by orthodox
Socialists, since they will find something repugnant to their principles
in the whole idea of a private person paying to have certain work done.
But it is a mistake to be the slave of a system, and every system, if it
is applied rigidly, will entail evils which could only be avoided by some
concession to the exigencies of special cases. On the whole, a wise form
of Socialism might afford infinitely better opportunities for the artist
and the man of science than are possible in a capitalist community, but
only if the form of Socialism adopted is one which is fitted for this end
by means of provisions such as we have been suggesting.</p>
<p>3. Possibility of Appreciation.—This condition is one which is not
necessary to all who do creative work, but in the sense in which I mean it
the great majority find it very nearly indispensable. I do not mean
widespread public recognition, nor that ignorant, half-sincere respect
which is commonly accorded to artists who have achieved success. Neither
of these serves much purpose. What I mean is rather understanding, and a
spontaneous feeling that things of beauty are important. In a thoroughly
commercialized society, an artist is respected if he makes money, and
because he makes money, but there is no genuine respect for the works of
art by which his money has been made. A millionaire whose fortune has been
made in button-hooks or chewing-gum is regarded with awe, but none of this
feeling is bestowed on the articles from which his wealth is derived. In a
society which measures all things by money the same tends to be true of
the artist. If he has become rich he is respected, though of course less
than the millionaire, but his pictures or books or music are regarded as
the chewing-gum or the button- hooks are regarded, merely as a means to
money. In such an atmosphere it is very difficult for the artist to
preserve his creative impulse pure: either he is contaminated by his
surroundings, or he becomes embittered through lack of appreciation for
the object of his endeavor.</p>
<p>It is not appreciation of the artist that is necessary so much as
appreciation of the art. It is difficult for an artist to live in an
environment in which everything is judged by its utility, rather than by
its intrinsic quality. The whole side of life of which art is the flower
requires something which may be called disinterestedness, a capacity for
direct enjoyment without thought of tomorrow's problems and difficulties.
When people are amused by a joke they do not need to be persuaded that it
will serve some important purpose. The same kind of direct pleasure is
involved in any genuine appreciation of art. The struggle for life, the
serious work of a trade or profession, is apt to make people too solemn
for jokes and too pre-occupied for art. The easing of the struggle, the
diminution in the hours of work, and the lightening of the burden of
existence, which would result from a better economic system, could hardly
fail to increase the joy of life and the vital energy, available for sheer
delight in the world. And if this were achieved there would inevitably be
more spontaneous pleasure in beautiful things, and more enjoyment of the
work of artists. But none of these good results are to be expected from
the mere removal of poverty: they all require also a diffused sense of
freedom, and the absence of that feeling of oppression by a vast machine
which now weighs down the individual spirit. I do not think State
Socialism can give this sense of freedom, but some other forms of
Socialism, which have absorbed what is true in Anarchist teaching, can
give it to a degree of which capitalism is wholly incapable.</p>
<p>A general sense of progress and achievement is an immense stimulus to all
forms of creative work. For this reason, a great deal will depend, not
only in material ways, upon the question whether methods of production in
industry and agriculture become stereotyped or continue to change rapidly
as they have done during the last hundred years. Improved methods of
production will be much more obviously than now to the interest of the
community at large, when what every man receives is his due share of the
total produce of labor. But there will probably not be any individuals
with the same direct and intense interest in technical improvements as now
belongs to the capitalist in manufacture. If the natural conservatism of
the workers is not to prove stronger than their interest in increasing
production, it will be necessary that, when better methods are introduced
by the workers in any industry, part at least of the benefit should be
allowed for a time to be retained by them. If this is done, it may be
presumed that each Guild will be continually seeking for new processes or
inventions, and will value those technical parts of scientific research
which are useful for this purpose. With every improvement, the question
will arise whether it is to be used to give more leisure or to increase
the dividend of commodities. Where there is so much more leisure than
there is now, there will be many more people with a knowledge of science
or an understanding of art. The artist or scientific investigator will be
far less cut off than he is at present from the average citizen, and this
will almost inevitably be a stimulus to his creative energy.</p>
<p>I think we may fairly conclude that, from the point of view of all three
requisites for art and science, namely, training, freedom and
appreciation, State Socialism would largely fail to remove existing evils
and would introduce new evils of its own; but Guild Socialism, or even
Syndicalism, if it adopted a liberal policy toward those who preferred to
work less than the usual number of hours at recognized occupations, might
be immeasurably preferable to anything that is possible under the rule of
capitalism. There are dangers, but they will all vanish if the importance
of liberty is adequately acknowledged. In this as in nearly everything
else, the road to all that is best is the road of freedom.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2HCH0008" id="link2HCH0008"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> CHAPTER VIII — THE WORLD AS IT COULD BE MADE </h2>
<p>IN the daily lives of most men and women, fear plays a greater part than
hope: they are more filled with the thought of the possessions that others
may take from them, than of the joy that they might create in their own
lives and in the lives with which they come in contact.</p>
<p>It is not so that life should be lived.</p>
<p>Those whose lives are fruitful to themselves, to their friends, or to the
world are inspired by hope and sustained by joy: they see in imagination
the things that might be and the way in which they are to be brought into
existence. In their private relations they are not pre-occupied with
anxiety lest they should lose such affection and respect as they receive:
they are engaged in giving affection and respect freely, and the reward
comes of itself without their seeking. In their work they are not haunted
by jealousy of competitors, but concerned with the actual matter that has
to be done. In politics, they do not spend time and passion defending
unjust privileges of their class or nation, but they aim at making the
world as a whole happier, less cruel, less full of conflict between rival
greeds, and more full of human beings whose growth has not been dwarfed
and stunted by oppression.</p>
<p>A life lived in this spirit—the spirit that aims at creating rather
than possessing—has a certain fundamental happiness, of which it
cannot be wholly robbed by adverse circumstances. This is the way of life
recommended in the Gospels, and by all the great teachers of the world.
Those who have found it are freed from the tyranny of fear, since what
they value most in their lives is not at the mercy of outside power. If
all men could summon up the courage and the vision to live in this way in
spite of obstacles and discouragement, there would be no need for the
regeneration of the world to begin by political and economic reform: all
that is needed in the way of reform would come automatically, without
resistance, owing to the moral regeneration of individuals. But the
teaching of Christ has been nominally accepted by the world for many
centuries, and yet those who follow it are still persecuted as they were
before the time of Constantine. Experience has proved that few are able to
see through the apparent evils of an outcast's life to the inner joy that
comes of faith and creative hope. If the domination of fear is to be
overcome, it is not enough, as regards the mass of men, to preach courage
and indifference to misfortune: it is necessary to remove the causes of
fear, to make a good life no longer an unsuccessful one in a worldly
sense, and to diminish the harm that can be inflicted upon those who are
not wary in self- defense.</p>
<p>When we consider the evils in the lives we know of, we find that they may
be roughly divided into three classes. There are, first, those due to
physical nature: among these are death, pain and the difficulty of making
the soil yield a subsistence. These we will call "physical evils." Second,
we may put those that spring from defects in the character or aptitudes of
the sufferer: among these are ignorance, lack of will, and violent
passions. These we will call "evils of character." Third come those that
depend upon the power of one individual or group over another: these
comprise not only obvious tyranny, but all interference with free
development, whether by force or by excessive mental influence such as may
occur in education. These we will call "evils of power." A social system
may be judged by its bearing upon these three kinds of evils.</p>
<p>The distinction between the three kinds cannot be sharply drawn. Purely
physical evil is a limit, which we can never be sure of having reached: we
cannot abolish death, but we can often postpone it by science, and it may
ultimately become possible to secure that the great majority shall live
till old age; we cannot wholly prevent pain, but we can diminish it
indefinitely by securing a healthy life for all; we cannot make the earth
yield its fruits in any abundance without labor, but we can diminish the
amount of the labor and improve its conditions until it ceases to be an
evil. Evils of character are often the result of physical evil in the
shape of illness, and still more often the result of evils of power, since
tyranny degrades both those who exercise it and (as a rule) those who
suffer it. Evils of power are intensified by evils of character in those
who have power, and by fear of the physical evil which is apt to be the
lot of those who have no power. For all these reasons, the three sorts of
evil are intertwined. Nevertheless, speaking broadly, we may distinguish
among our misfortunes those which have their proximate cause in the
material world, those which are mainly due to defects in ourselves, and
those which spring from our being subject to the control of others.</p>
<p>The main methods of combating these evils are: for physical evils,
science; for evils of character, education (in the widest sense) and a
free outlet for all impulses that do not involve domination; for evils of
power, the reform of the political and economic organization of society in
such a way as to reduce to the lowest possible point the interference of
one man with the life of another. We will begin with the third of these
kinds of evil, because it is evils of power specially that Socialism and
Anarchism have sought to remedy. Their protest against Inequalities of
wealth has rested mainly upon their sense of the evils arising from the
power conferred by wealth. This point has been well stated by Mr. G. D. H.
Cole:—</p>
<p>What, I want to ask, is the fundamental evil in our modern Society which
we should set out to abolish?</p>
<p>There are two possible answers to that question, and I am sure that very
many well-meaning people would make the wrong one. They would answer
POVERTY, when they ought to answer SLAVERY. Face to face every day with
the shameful contrasts of riches and destitution, high dividends and low
wages, and painfully conscious of the futility of trying to adjust the
balance by means of charity, private or public, they would answer
unhesitatingly that they stand for the ABOLITION OF POVERTY.</p>
<p>Well and good! On that issue every Socialist is with them. But their
answer to my question is none the less wrong.</p>
<p>Poverty is the symptom: slavery the disease. The extremes of riches and
destitution follow inevitably upon the extremes of license and bondage.
The many are not enslaved because they are poor, they are poor because
they are enslaved. Yet Socialists have all too often fixed their eyes upon
the material misery of the poor without realizing that it rests upon the
spiritual degradation of the slave.<SPAN href="#linknote-59"
name="linknoteref-59" id="linknoteref-59"><small>59</small></SPAN></p>
<p>I do not think any reasonable person can doubt that the evils of power in
the present system are vastly greater than is necessary, nor that they
might be immeasurably diminished by a suitable form of Socialism. A few
fortunate people, it is true, are now enabled to live freely on rent or
interest, and they could hardly have more liberty under another system.
But the great bulk, not only of the very poor, but, of all sections of
wage-earners and even of the professional classes, are the slaves of the
need for getting money. Almost all are compelled to work so hard that they
have little leisure for enjoyment or for pursuits outside their regular
occupation. Those who are able to retire in later middle age are bored,
because they have not learned how to fill their time when they are at
liberty, and such interests as they once had apart from work have dried
up. Yet these are the exceptionally fortunate: the majority have to work
hard till old age, with the fear of destitution always before them, the
richer ones dreading that they will be unable to give their children the
education or the medical care that they consider desirable, the poorer
ones often not far removed from starvation. And almost all who work have
no voice in the direction of their work; throughout the hours of labor
they are mere machines carrying out the will of a master. Work is usually
done under disagreeable conditions, involving pain and physical hardship.
The only motive to work is wages: the very idea that work might be a joy,
like the work of the artist, is usually scouted as utterly Utopian.</p>
<p>But by far the greater part of these evils are wholly unnecessary. If the
civilized portion of mankind could be induced to desire their own
happiness more than another's pain, if they could be induced to work
constructively for improvements which they would share with all the world
rather than destructively to prevent other classes or nations from
stealing a march on them, the whole system by which the world's work is
done might be reformed root and branch within a generation.</p>
<p>From the point of view of liberty, what system would be the best? In what
direction should we wish the forces of progress to move?</p>
<p>From this point of view, neglecting for the moment all other
considerations, I have no doubt that the best system would be one not far
removed from that advocated by Kropotkin, but rendered more practicable by
the adoption of the main principles of Guild Socialism. Since every point
can be disputed, I will set down without argument the kind of organization
of work that would seem best.</p>
<p>Education should be compulsory up to the age of 16, or perhaps longer;
after that, it should be continued or not at the option of the pupil, but
remain free (for those who desire it) up to at least the age of 21. When
education is finished no one should be COMPELLED to work, and those who
choose not to work should receive a bare livelihood, and be left
completely free; but probably it would be desirable that there should be a
strong public opinion in favor of work, so that only comparatively few
should choose idleness. One great advantage of making idleness
economically possible is that it would afford a powerful motive for making
work not disagreeable; and no community where most work is disagreeable
can be said to have found a solution of economic problems. I think it is
reasonable to assume that few would choose idleness, in view of the fact
that even now at least nine out of ten of those who have (say) 100 pounds
a year from investments prefer to increase their income by paid work.</p>
<p>Coming now to that great majority who will not choose idleness, I think we
may assume that, with the help of science, and by the elimination of the
vast amount of unproductive work involved in internal and international
competition, the whole community could be kept in comfort by means of four
hours' work a day. It is already being urged by experienced employers that
their employes can actually produce as much in a six-hour day as they can
when they work eight hours. In a world where there is a much higher level
of technical instruction than there is now the same tendency will be
accentuated. People will be taught not only, as at present, one trade, or
one small portion of a trade, but several trades, so that they can vary
their occupation according to the seasons and the fluctuations of demand.
Every industry will be self-governing as regards all its internal affairs,
and even separate factories will decide for themselves all questions that
only concern those who work in them. There will not be capitalist
management, as at present, but management by elected representatives, as
in politics. Relations between different groups of producers will be
settled by the Guild Congress, matters concerning the community as the
inhabitants of a certain area will continue to be decided by Parliament,
while all disputes between Parliament and the Guild Congress will be
decided by a body composed of representatives of both in equal numbers.</p>
<p>Payment will not be made, as at present, only for work actually required
and performed, but for willingness to work. This system is already adopted
in much of the better paid work: a man occupies a certain position, and
retains it even at times when there happens to be very little to do. The
dread of unemployment and loss of livelihood will no longer haunt men like
a nightmare. Whether all who are willing to work will be paid equally, or
whether exceptional skill will still command exceptional pay, is a matter
which may be left to each guild to decide for itself. An opera-singer who
received no more pay than a scene-shifter might choose to be a
scene-shifter until the system was changed: if so, higher pay would
probably be found necessary. But if it were freely voted by the Guild, it
could hardly constitute a grievance.</p>
<p>Whatever might be done toward making work agreeable, it is to be presumed
that some trades would always remain unpleasant. Men could be attracted
into these by higher pay or shorter hours, instead of being driven into
them by destitution. The community would then have a strong economic
motive for finding ways of diminishing the disagreeableness of these
exceptional trades.</p>
<p>There would still have to be money, or something analogous to it, in any
community such as we are imagining. The Anarchist plan of a free
distribution of the total produce of work in equal shares does not get rid
of the need for some standard of exchange value, since one man will choose
to take his share in one form and another in another. When the day comes
for distributing luxuries, old ladies will not want their quota of cigars,
nor young men their just proportion of lap-dog; this will make it
necessary to know how many cigars are the equivalent of one lap-dog. Much
the simplest way is to pay an income, as at present, and allow relative
values to be adjusted according to demand. But if actual coin were paid, a
man might hoard it and in time become a capitalist. To prevent this, it
would be best to pay notes available only during a certain period, say one
year from the date of issue. This would enable a man to save up for his
annual holiday, but not to save indefinitely.</p>
<p>There is a very great deal to be said for the Anarchist plan of allowing
necessaries, and all commodities that can easily be produced in quantities
adequate to any possible demand, to be given away freely to all who ask
for them, in any amounts they may require. The question whether this plan
should be adopted is, to my mind, a purely technical one: would it be, in
fact, possible to adopt it without much waste and consequent diversion of
labor to the production of necessaries when it might be more usefully
employed otherwise? I have not the means of answering this question, but I
think it exceedingly probable that, sooner or later, with the continued
improvement in the methods of production, this Anarchist plan will become
feasible; and when it does, it certainly ought to be adopted.</p>
<p>Women in domestic work, whether married or unmarried, will receive pay as
they would if they were in industry. This will secure the complete
economic independence of wives, which is difficult to achieve in any other
way, since mothers of young children ought not to be expected to work
outside the home.</p>
<p>The expense of children will not fall, as at present, on the parents. They
will receive, like adults, their share of necessaries, and their education
will be free.<SPAN href="#linknote-60" name="linknoteref-60" id="linknoteref-60"><small>60</small></SPAN> There is no longer to be the
present competition for scholarships among the abler children: they will
not be imbued with the competitive spirit from infancy, or forced to use
their brains to an unnatural degree with consequent listlessness and lack
of health in later life. Education will be far more diversified than at
present; greater care will be taken to adapt it to the needs of different
types of young people. There will be more attempt to encourage initiative
young pupils, and less desire to fill their minds with a set of beliefs
and mental habits regarded as desirable by the State, chiefly because they
help to preserve the status quo. For the great majority of children it
will probably be found desirable to have much more outdoor education in
the country. And for older boys and girls whose interests are not
intellectual or artistic, technical education, undertaken in a liberal
spirit, is far more useful in promoting mental activity than book-learning
which they regard (however falsely) as wholly useless except for purposes
of examination. The really useful educa- tion is that which follows the
direction of the child's own instinctive interests, supplying knowledge
for which it is seeking, not dry, detailed information wholly out of
relation to its spontaneous desires.</p>
<p>Government and law will still exist in our community, but both will be
reduced to a minimum. There will still be acts which will be forbidden—for
example, murder. But very nearly the whole of that part of the criminal
law which deals with property will have become obsolete, and many of the
motives which now produce murders will be no longer operative. Those who
nevertheless still do commit crimes will not be blamed or regarded as
wicked; they will be regarded as unfortunate, and kept in some kind of
mental hospital until it is thought that they are no longer a danger. By
education and freedom and the abolition of private capital the number of
crimes can be made exceedingly small. By the method of individual curative
treatment it will generally be possible to secure that a man's first
offense shall also be his last, except in the case of lunatics and the
feeble-minded, for whom of course a more prolonged but not less kindly
detention may be necessary.</p>
<p>Government may be regarded as consisting of two parts: the one, the
decisions of the community or its recognized organs; the other, the
enforcing of those decisions upon all who resist them. The first part is
not objected to by Anarchists. The second part, in an ordinary civilized
State, may remain entirely in the background: those who have resisted a
new law while it was being debated will, as a rule, submit to it when it
is passed, because resistance is generally useless in a settled and
orderly community. But the possibility of governmental force remains, and
indeed is the very reason for the submission which makes force
unnecessary. If, as Anarchists desire, there were no use of force by
government, the majority could still band themselves together and use
force against the minority. The only difference would be that their army
or their police force would be ad hoc, instead of being permanent and
professional. The result of this would be that everyone would have to
learn how to fight, for fear a well- drilled minority should seize power
and establish an old-fashioned oligarchic State. Thus the aim of the
Anarchists seems hardly likely to be achieved by the methods which they
advocate.</p>
<p>The reign of violence in human affairs, whether within a country or in its
external relations, can only be prevented, if we have not been mistaken,
by an authority able to declare all use of force except by itself illegal,
and strong enough to be obviously capable of making all other use of force
futile, except when it could secure the support of public opinion as a
defense of freedom or a resistance to injustice. Such an authority exists
within a country: it is the State. But in international affairs it remains
to be created. The difficulties are stupendous, but they must be overcome
if the world is to be saved from periodical wars, each more destructive
than any of its predecessors. Whether, after this war, a League of Nations
will be formed, and will be capable of performing this task, it is as yet
impossible to foretell. However that may be, some method of preventing
wars will have to be established before our Utopia becomes possible. When
once men BELIEVE that the world is safe from war, the whole difficulty
will be solved: there will then no longer be any serious resistance to the
disbanding of national armies and navies, and the substitution for them of
a small international force for protection against uncivilized races. And
when that stage has been reached, peace will be virtually secure.</p>
<p>The practice of government by majorities, which Anarchists criticise, is
in fact open to most of the objections which they urge against it. Still
more objectionable is the power of the executive in matters vitally
affecting the happiness of all, such as peace and war. But neither can be
dispensed with suddenly. There are, however, two methods of diminishing
the harm done by them: (1) Government by majorities can be made less
oppressive by devolution, by placing the decision of questions primarily
affecting only a section of the community in the hands of that section,
rather than of a Central Chamber. In this way, men are no longer forced to
submit to decisions made in a hurry by people mostly ignorant of the
matter in hand and not personally interested. Autonomy for internal
affairs should be given, not only to areas, but to all groups, such as
industries or Churches, which have important common interests not shared
by the rest of the community. (2) The great powers vested in the executive
of a modern State are chiefly due to the frequent need of rapid decisions,
especially as regards foreign affairs. If the danger of war were
practically eliminated, more cumbrous but less autocratic methods would be
possible, and the Legislature might recover many of the powers which the
executive has usurped. By these two methods, the intensity of the
interference with liberty involved in government can be gradually
diminished. Some interference, and even some danger of unwarranted and
despotic interference, is of the essence of government, and must remain so
long as government remains. But until men are less prone to violence than
they are now, a certain degree of governmental force seems the lesser of
two evils. We may hope, however, that if once the danger of war is at an
end, men's violent impulses will gradually grow less, the more so as, in
that case, it will be possible to diminish enormously the individual power
which now makes rulers autocratic and ready for almost any act of tyranny
in order to crush opposition. The development of a world where even
governmental force has become unnecessary (except against lunatics) must
be gradual. But as a gradual process it is perfectly possible; and when it
has been completed we may hope to see the principles of Anarchism embodied
in the management of communal affairs.</p>
<p>How will the economic and political system that we have outlined bear on
the evils of character? I believe the effect will be quite extraordinarily
beneficent.</p>
<p>The process of leading men's thought and imagination away from the use of
force will be greatly accelerated by the abolition of the capitalist
system, provided it is not succeeded by a form of State Socialism in which
officials have enormous power. At present, the capitalist has more control
over the lives of others than any man ought to have; his friends have
authority in the State; his economic power is the pattern for political
power. In a world where all men and women enjoy economic freedom, there
will not be the same habit of command, nor, consequently, the same love of
despotism; a gentler type of character than that now prevalent will
gradually grow up. Men are formed by their circumstances, not born ready-
made. The bad effect of the present economic system on character, and the
immensely better effect to be expected from communal ownership, are among
the strongest reasons for advocating the change.</p>
<p>In the world as we have been imagining fit, economic fear and most
economic hope will be alike removed out of life. No one will be haunted by
the dread of poverty or driven into ruthlessness by the hope of wealth.
There will not be the distinction of social classes which now plays such
an immense part in life. The unsuccessful professional man will not live
in terror lest his children should sink in the scale; the aspiring employe
will not be looking forward to the day when he can become a sweater in his
turn. Ambitious young men will have to dream other daydreams than that of
business success and wealth wrung out of the ruin of competitors and the
degradation of labor. In such a world, most of the nightmares that lurk in
the background of men's minds will no longer exist; on the other hand,
ambition and the desire to excel will have to take nobler forms than those
that are encouraged by a commercial society. All those activities that
really confer benefits upon mankind will be open, not only to the
fortunate few, but to all who have sufficient ambition and native
aptitude. Science, labor-saving inventions, technical progress of all
kinds, may be confidently expected to flourish far more than at present,
since they will be the road to honor, and honor will have to replace money
among those of the young who desire to achieve success. Whether art will
flourish in a Socialistic community depends upon the form of Social- ism
adopted; if the State, or any public authority, (no matter what), insists
upon controlling art, and only licensing those whom it regards as
proficient, the result will be disaster. But if there is real freedom,
allowing every man who so desires to take up an artist's career at the
cost of some sacrifice of comfort, it is likely that the atmosphere of
hope, and the absence of economic compulsion, will lead to a much smaller
waste of talent than is involved in our present system, and to a much less
degree of crushing of impulse in the mills of the struggle for life.</p>
<p>When elementary needs have been satisfied, the serious happiness of most
men depends upon two things: their work, and their human relations. In the
world that we have been picturing, work will be free, not excessive, full
of the interest that belongs to a collective enterprise in which there is
rapid progress, with something of the delight of creation even for the
humblest unit. And in human relations the gain will be just as great as in
work. The only human relations that have value are those that are rooted
in mutual freedom, where there is no domination and no slavery, no tie
except affection, no economic or conventional necessity to preserve the
external show when the inner life is dead. One of the most horrible things
about commercialism is the way in which it poisons the relations of men
and women. The evils of prostitution are generally recognized, but, great
as they are, the effect of economic conditions on marriage seems to me
even worse. There is not infrequently, in marriage, a suggestion of
purchase, of acquiring a woman on condition of keeping her in a certain
standard of material comfort. Often and often, a marriage hardly differs
from prostitution except by being harder to escape from. The whole basis
of these evils is economic. Economic causes make marriage a matter of
bargain and contract, in which affection is quite secondary, and its
absence constitutes no recognized reason for liberation. Marriage should
be a free, spontaneous meeting of mutual instinct, filled with happiness
not unmixed with a feeling akin to awe: it should involve that degree of
respect of each for the other that makes even the most trifling
interference with liberty an utter impossibility, and a common life
enforced by one against the will of the other an unthinkable thing of deep
horror. It is not so that marriage is conceived by lawyers who make
settlements, or by priests who give the name of "sacrament" to an
institution which pretends to find something sanctifiable in the brutal
lusts or drunken cruelties of a legal husband. It is not in a spirit of
freedom that marriage is conceived by most men and women at present: the
law makes it an opportunity for indulgence of the desire to interfere,
where each submits to some loss of his or her own liberty, for the
pleasure of curtailing the liberty of the other. And the atmosphere of
private property makes it more difficult than it otherwise would be for
any better ideal to take root.</p>
<p>It is not so that human relations will be conceived when the evil heritage
of economic slavery has ceased to mold our instincts. Husbands and wives,
parents and children, will be only held together by affection: where that
has died, it will be recognized that nothing worth preserving is left.
Because affection will be free, men and women will not find in private
life an outlet and stimulus to the love of domineering, but all that is
creative in their love will have the freer scope. Reverence for whatever
makes the soul in those who are loved will be less rare than it is now:
nowadays, many men love their wives in the way in which they love mutton,
as something to devour and destroy. But in the love that goes with
reverence there is a joy of quite another order than any to be found by
mastery, a joy which satisfies the spirit and not only the instincts; and
satisfaction of instinct and spirit at once is necessary to a happy life,
or indeed to any existence that is to bring out the best impulses of which
a man or woman is capable.</p>
<p>In the world which we should wish to see, there will be more joy of life
than in the drab tragedy of modern every-day existence. After early youth,
as things are, most men are bowed down by forethought, no longer capable
of light-hearted gaiety, but only of a kind of solemn jollification by the
clock at the appropriate hours. The advice to "become as little children"
would be good for many people in many respects, but it goes with another
precept, "take no thought for the morrow," which is hard to obey in a
competitive world. There is often in men of science, even when they are
quite old, something of the simplicity of a child: their absorption in
abstract thought has held them aloof from the world, and respect for their
work has led the world to keep them alive in spite of their innocence.
Such men have succeeded in living as all men ought to be able to live; but
as things are, the economic struggle makes their way of life impossible
for the great majority.</p>
<p>What are we to say, lastly, of the effect of our projected world upon
physical evil? Will there be less illness than there is at present? Will
the produce of a given amount of labor be greater? Or will population
press upon the limits of subsistence, as Malthus taught in order to refute
Godwin's optimism?</p>
<p>I think the answer to all these questions turns, in the end, upon the
degree of intellectual vigor to be expected in a community which has done
away with the spur of economic competition. Will men in such a world
become lazy and apathetic? Will they cease to think? Will those who do
think find themselves confronted with an even more impenetrable wall of
unreflecting conservatism than that which confronts them at present? These
are important questions; for it is ultimately to science that mankind must
look for their success in combating physical evils.</p>
<p>If the other conditions that we have postulated can be realized, it seems
almost certain that there must be less illness than there is at present.
Population will no longer be congested in slums; children will have far
more of fresh air and open country; the hours of work will be only such as
are wholesome, not excessive and exhausting as they are at present.</p>
<p>As for the progress of science, that depends very largely upon the degree
of intellectual liberty existing in the new society. If all science is
organized and supervised by the State, it will rapidly become stereotyped
and dead. Fundamental advances will not be made, because, until they have
been made, they will seem too doubtful to warrant the expenditure of
public money upon them. Authority will be in the hands of the old,
especially of men who have achieved scientific eminence; such men will be
hostile to those among the young who do not flatter them by agreeing with
their theories. Under a bureaucratic State Socialism it is to be feared
that science would soon cease to be progressive and acquired a medieval
respect for authority.</p>
<p>But under a freer system, which would enable all kinds of groups to employ
as many men of science as they chose, and would allow the "vagabond's
wage" to those who desired to pursue some study so new as to be wholly
unrecognized, there is every reason to think that science would flourish
as it has never done hitherto.<SPAN href="#linknote-61" name="linknoteref-61" id="linknoteref-61"><small>61</small></SPAN> And, if that were the case, I do
not believe that any other obstacle would exist to the physical
possibility of our system.</p>
<p>The question of the number of hours of work necessary to produce general
material comfort is partly technical, partly one of organization. We may
assume that there would no longer be unproductive labor spent on
armaments, national defense, advertisements, costly luxuries for the very
rich, or any of the other futilities incidental to our competitive system.
If each industrial guild secured for a term of years the advantages, or
part of the advantages, of any new invention or methods which it
introduced, it is pretty certain that every encouragement would be given
to technical progress. The life of a discoverer or inventor is in itself
agreeable: those who adopt it, as things are now, are seldom much actuated
by economic motives, but rather by the interest of the work together with
the hope of honor; and these motives would operate more widely than they
do now, since fewer people would be prevented from obeying them by
economic necessities. And there is no doubt that intellect would work more
keenly and creatively in a world where instinct was less thwarted, where
the joy of life was greater, and where consequently there would be more
vitality in men than there is at present.</p>
<p>There remains the population question, which, ever since the time of
Malthus, has been the last refuge of those to whom the possibility of a
better world is disagreeable. But this question is now a very different
one from what it was a hundred years ago. The decline of the birth-rate in
all civilized countries, which is pretty certain to continue, whatever
economic system is adopted, suggests that, especially when the probable
effects of the war are taken into account, the population of Western
Europe is not likely to increase very much beyond its present level, and
that of America is likely only to increase through immigration. Negroes
may continue to increase in the tropics, but are not likely to be a
serious menace to the white inhabitants of temperate regions. There
remains, of course, the Yellow Peril; but by the time that begins to be
serious it is quite likely that the birth-rate will also have begun to
decline among the races of Asia If not, there are other means of dealing
with this question; and in any case the whole matter is too conjectural to
be set up seriously as a bar to our hopes. I conclude that, though no
certain forecast is possible, there is not any valid reason for regarding
the possible increase of population as a serious obstacle to Socialism.</p>
<p>Our discussion has led us to the belief that the communal ownership of
land and capital, which constitutes the characteristic doctrine of
Socialism and Anarchist Communism, is a necessary step toward the removal
of the evils from which the world suffers at present and the creation of
such a society as any humane man must wish to see realized. But, though a
necessary step, Socialism alone is by no means sufficient. There are
various forms of Socialism: the form in which the State is the employer,
and all who work receive wages from it, involves dangers of tyranny and
interference with progress which would make it, if possible, even worse
than the present regime. On the other hand, Anarchism, which avoids the
dangers of State Socialism, has dangers and difficulties of its own, which
make it probable that, within any reasonable period of time, it could not
last long even if it were established. Nevertheless, it remains an ideal
to which we should wish to approach as nearly as possible, and which, in
some distant age, we hope may be reached completely. Syndicalism shares
many of the defects of Anarchism, and, like it, would prove unstable,
since the need of a central government would make itself felt almost at
once.</p>
<p>The system we have advocated is a form of Guild Socialism, leaning more,
perhaps, towards Anarchism than the official Guildsman would wholly
approve. It is in the matters that politicians usually ignore—
science and art, human relations, and the joy of life —that
Anarchism is strongest, and it is chiefly for the sake of these things
that we included such more or less Anarchist proposals as the "vagabond's
wage." It is by its effects outside economics and politics, at least as
much as by effects inside them, that a social system should be judged. And
if Socialism ever comes, it is only likely to prove beneficent if non-
economic goods are valued and consciously pursued.</p>
<p>The world that we must seek is a world in which the creative spirit is
alive, in which life is an adventure full of joy and hope, based rather
upon the impulse to construct than upon the desire to retain what we
possess or to seize what is possessed by others. It must be a world in
which affection has free play, in which love is purged of the instinct for
domination, in which cruelty and envy have been dispelled by happiness and
the unfettered development of all the instincts that build up life and
fill it with mental delights. Such a world is possible; it waits only for
men to wish to create it.</p>
<p>Meantime, the world in which we exist has other aims. But it will pass
away, burned up in the fire of its own hot passions; and from its ashes
will spring a new and younger world, full of fresh hope, with the light of
morning in its eyes.</p>
<p><br/><br/></p>
<hr />
<p><SPAN name="link2H_FOOT" id="link2H_FOOT"> </SPAN></p>
<br/>
<h2> FOOTNOTES: </h2>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-1" id="linknote-1"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
1 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-1">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Chief among these were
Fourier and Saint-Simon, who constructed somewhat fantastic Socialistic
ideal commonwealths. Proudhon, with whom Marx had some not wholly friendly
relations, is to be regarded as a forerunner of the Anarchists rather than
of orthodox Socialism.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-2" id="linknote-2"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
2 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-2">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Marx mentions the English
Socialists with praise in "The Poverty of Philosophy" (1847). They, like
him, tend to base their arguments upon a Ricardian theory of value, but
they have not his scope or erudition or scientific breadth. Among them may
be mentioned Thomas Hodgskin (1787-1869), originally an officer in the
Navy, but dismissed for a pamphlet critical of the methods of naval
discipline, author of "Labour Defended Against the Claims of Capital"
(1825) and other works; William Thompson (1785-1833), author of "Inquiry
into the Principles of Distribution of Wealth Most Conducive to Human
Happiness" (1824), and "Labour Rewarded" (1825); and Piercy Ravenstone,
from whom Hodgskin's ideas are largely derived. Perhaps more important
than any of these was Robert Owen.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-3" id="linknote-3"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
3 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-3">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ The first and most
important volume appeared in 1867; the other two volumes were published
posthumously (1885 and 1894).]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-4" id="linknote-4"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
4 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-4">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Vol. i, p. 227.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-5" id="linknote-5"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
5 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-5">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Vol. i, pp. 237, 238.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-6" id="linknote-6"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
6 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-6">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Vol. i, pp. 239, 240.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-7" id="linknote-7"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
7 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-7">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Vol. i, pp. 758, 759.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-8" id="linknote-8"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
8 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-8">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Vol. i pp. 788, 789.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-9" id="linknote-9"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
9 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-9">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Die Voraussetzungen des
Sozialismus und die Aufgaben der Sozial-Demokratie."]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-10" id="linknote-10"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
10 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-10">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ La Decomposition du
Marxisme," p. 53.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-11" id="linknote-11"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
11 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-11">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "Musings of a Chinese
Mystic." Selections from the Philosophy of Chuang Tzu. With an
Introduction by Lionel Giles, M.A. (Oxon.). Wisdom of the East Series,
John Murray, 1911. Pages 66-68.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-12" id="linknote-12"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
12 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-12">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ An account of the life of
Bakunin from the Anarchist standpoint will be found in vol. ii of the
complete edition of his works: "Michel Bakounine, OEuvres," Tome II. Avec
une notice biographique, des avant-propos et des notes, par James
Guillaume. Paris, P.-V, Stock, editeur, pp. v-lxiii.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-13" id="linknote-13"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
13 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-13">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Criticism of these
theories will be reserved for Part II.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-14" id="linknote-14"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
14 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-14">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Ibid. p. xxvi.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-15" id="linknote-15"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
15 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-15">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "Marx, as a thinker, is
on the right road. He has established as a principle that all the
evolutions, political, religious, and juridical, in history are, not the
causes, but the effects of economic evolutions. This is a great and
fruitful thought, which he has not absolutely invented; it has been
glimpsed, expressed in part, by many others besides him; but in any case
to him belongs the honor of having solidly established it and of having
enunciated it as the basis of his whole economic system. (1870; ib. ii. p.
xiii.)]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-16" id="linknote-16"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
16 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-16">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ This title is not
Bakunin's, but was invented by Cafiero and Elisee Reclus, who edited it,
not knowing that it was a fragment of what was intended to he the second
version of "L'Empire Knouto-Germanique" (see ib. ii. p 283).]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-17" id="linknote-17"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
17 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-17">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Paris, 1894.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-18" id="linknote-18"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
18 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-18">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ The attitude of all the
better Anarchists is that expressed by L. S. Bevington in the words: "Of
course we know that among those who call themselves Anarchists there are a
minority of unbalanced enthusiasts who look upon every illegal and
sensational act of violence as a matter for hysterical jubilation. Very
useful to the police and the press, unsteady in intellect and of weak
moral principle, they have repeatedly shown themselves accessible to venal
considerations. They, and their violence, and their professed Anarchism
are purchasable, and in the last resort they are welcome and efficient
partisans of the bourgeoisie in its remorseless war against the deliverers
of the people." His conclusion is a very wise one: "Let us leave
indiscriminate killing and injuring to the Government—to its
Statesmen, its Stockbrokers, its Officers, and its Law." ("Anarchism and
Violence," pp. 9-10. Liberty Press, Chiswick, 1896.)]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-19" id="linknote-19"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
19 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-19">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ See next Chapter.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-20" id="linknote-20"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
20 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-20">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Of which the Independent
Labor Party is only a section.]</p>
<p>And also in Italy. A good, short account of the Italian movement is given
by A. Lanzillo, "Le Mouvement Ouvrier en Italie," Bibliotheque du
Mouvement Proletarien. See also Paul Louis, "Le Syndicalisme Europeen,"
chap. vi. On the other hand Cole ("World of Labour," chap. vi) considers
the strength of genuine Syndicalism in Italy to be small.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-21" id="linknote-21"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
21 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-21">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ This is often recognized
by Syndicalists themselves. See, e.g., an article on "The Old
International" in the Syndicalist of February, 1913, which, after giving
an account of the struggle between Marx and Bakunin from the standpoint of
a sympathizer with the latter, says: "Bakounin's ideas are now more alive
than ever."]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-22" id="linknote-22"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
22 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-22">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ See pp. 42-43, and 160 of
"Syndicalism in France," Louis Levine, Ph.D. (Columbia University Studies
in Political Science, vol. xlvi, No. 3.) This is a very objective and
reliable account of the origin and progress of French Syndicalism. An
admirable short discussion of its ideas and its present position will be
found in Cole's "World of Labour" (G. Bell & Sons), especially
chapters iii, iv, and xi.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-23" id="linknote-23"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
23 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-23">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ See Levine, op. cit.,
chap. ii.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-24" id="linknote-24"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
24 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-24">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Cole, ib., p. 65.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-25" id="linknote-25"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
25 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-25">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "Syndicat in France still
means a local union—there are at the present day only four national
syndicats" (ib., p. 66).]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-26" id="linknote-26"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
26 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-26">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Cole, ib. p. 69.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-27" id="linknote-27"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
27 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-27">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ In fact the General
Strike was invented by a Londoner William Benbow, an Owenite, in 1831.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-28" id="linknote-28"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
28 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-28">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "World of Labour," pp.
212, 213.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-29" id="linknote-29"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
29 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-29">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Quoted in Cole, ib. p.
128.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-30" id="linknote-30"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
30 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-30">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Ib., p. 135.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-31" id="linknote-31"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
31 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-31">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Brooks, op. cit., p. 79.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-32" id="linknote-32"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
32 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-32">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Brooks, op. cit., pp.
86-87.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-34" id="linknote-34"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
34 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-34">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Literary Digest, May 2
and May 16, 1914.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-36" id="linknote-36"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
36 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-36">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ The above quotations are
all from the first pamphlet of the National Guilds League, "National
Guilds, an Appeal to Trade Unionists."]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-35" id="linknote-35"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
35 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-35">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ The ideas of Guild
Socialism were first set forth in "National Guilds," edited by A. R. Orage
(Bell & Sons, 1914), and in Cole's "World of Labour" (Bell &
Sons), first published in 1913. Cole's "Self-Government in Industry" (Bell
& Sons, 1917) and Rickett & Bechhofer's "The Meaning of National
Guilds" (Palmer & Hayward, 1918) should also be read, as well as
various pamphlets published by the National Guilds League. The attitude of
the Syndicalists to Guild Socialism is far from sympathetic. An article in
"The Syndicalist" for February, 1914, speaks of it in the following terms:
a Middle-class of the middle-class, with all the shortcomings (we had
almost said `stupidities') of the middle- classes writ large across it,
`Guild Socialism' stands forth as the latest lucubration of the
middle-class mind. It is a `cool steal' of the leading ideas of
Syndicalism and a deliberate perversion of them. . . . We do protest
against the `State' idea . . . in Guild Socialism. Middle-class people,
even when they become Socialists, cannot get rid of the idea that the
working-class is their `inferior'; that the workers need to be `educated,'
drilled, disciplined, and generally nursed for a very long time before
they will be able to walk by themselves. The very reverse is actually the
truth. . . . It is just the plain truth when we say that the ordinary
wage-worker, of average intelligence, is better capable of taking care of
himself than the half-educated middle-class man who wants to advise him.
He knows how to make the wheels of the world go round."]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-37" id="linknote-37"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
37 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-37">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "The Guild Idea," No. 2
of the Pamphlets of the National Guilds League, p. 17.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-38" id="linknote-38"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
38 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-38">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Kropotkin, "Fields,
Factories and Workshops," p. 74.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-39" id="linknote-39"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
39 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-39">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Ib. p. 81.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-40" id="linknote-40"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
40 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-40">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Kropotkin, "Field,
Factories, and Workshops," p. 6.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-41" id="linknote-41"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
41 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-41">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "Notwithstanding the
egotistic turn given to the public mind by the merchant-production of our
century, the Communist tendency is continually reasserting itself and
trying to make its way into public life. The penny bridge disappears
before the public bridge; and the turnpike road before the free road. The
same spirit pervades thousands of other institutions. Museums, free
libraries, and free public schools; parks and pleasure grounds; paved and
lighted streets, free for everybody's use; water supplied to private
dwellings, with a growing tendency towards disregarding the exact amount
of it used by the individual, tramways and railways which have already
begun to introduce the season ticket or the uniform tax, and will surely
go much further on this line when they are no longer private property: all
these are tokens showing in what direction further progress is to be
expected."—Kropotkin, "Anarchist Communism."]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-42" id="linknote-42"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
42 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-42">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ An able discussion of
this question, at of various others, from the standpoint of reasoned and
temperate opposition to Anarchism, will be found in Alfred Naquet's
"L'Anarchie et le Collectivisme," Paris, 1904.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-43" id="linknote-43"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
43 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-43">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "Overwork is repulsive to
human nature—not work. Overwork for supplying the few with luxury—not
work for the well- being of all. Work, labor, is a physiological
necessity, a necessity of spending accumulated bodily energy, a necessity
which is health and life itself. If so many branches of useful work are so
reluctantly done now, it is merely because they mean overwork, or they are
improperly organized. But we know—old Franklin knew it—that
four hours of useful work every day would be more than sufficient for
supplying everybody with the comfort of a moderately well-to-do
middle-class house, if we all gave ourselves to productive work, and if we
did not waste our productive powers as we do waste them now. As to the
childish question, repeated for fifty years: `Who would do disagreeable
work?' frankly I regret that none of our savants has ever been brought to
do it, be it for only one day in his life. If there is still work which is
really disagreeable in itself, it is only because our scientific men have
never cared to consider the means of rendering it less so: they have
always known that there were plenty of starving men who would do it for a
few pence a day." Kropotkin, "`Anarchist Communism."]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-44" id="linknote-44"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
44 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-44">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "As to the so-often
repeated objection that nobody would labor if he were not compelled to do
so by sheer necessity, we heard enough of it before the emancipation of
slaves in America, as well as before the emancipation of serfs in Russia;
and we have had the opportunity of appreciating it at its just value. So
we shall not try to convince those who can be convinced only by
accomplished facts. As to those who reason, they ought to know that, if it
really was so with some parts of humanity at its lowest stages—and
yet, what do we know about it?—or if it is so with some small
communities, or separate individuals, brought to sheer despair by
ill-success in their struggle against unfavorable conditions, it is not so
with the bulk of the civilized nations. With us, work is a habit, and
idleness an artificial growth." Kropotkin, "Anarchist Communism," p. 30.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-45" id="linknote-45"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
45 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-45">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "While holding this
synthetic view on production, the Anarchists cannot consider, like the
Collectivists, that a remuneration which would be proportionate to the
hours of labor spent by each person in the production of riches may be an
ideal, or even an approach to an ideal, society." Kropotkin, "Anarchist
Communism," p. 20.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-46" id="linknote-46"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
46 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-46">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ I do not say freedom is
the greatest of ALL goods: the best things come from within—they are
such things as creative art, and love, and thought. Such things can be
helped or hindered by political conditions, but not actually produced by
them; and freedom is, both in itself and in its relation to these other
goods the best thing that political and economic conditions can secure.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-47" id="linknote-47"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
47 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-47">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Communist Manifesto, p.
22.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-48" id="linknote-48"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
48 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-48">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "On the other hand, the
STATE has also been confused with GOVERNMENT. As there can be no State
without government, it has been sometimes said that it is the absence of
government, and not the abolition of the State, that should be the aim.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-49" id="linknote-49"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
49 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-49">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Representative government
has accomplished its historical mission; it has given a mortal blow to
Court-rule; and by its debates it has awakened public interest in public
questions. But, to see in it the government of the future Socialist
society, is to commit a gross error. Each economical phase of life implies
its own political phase; and it is impossible to touch the very basis of
the present economical life—private property— without a
corresponding change in the very basis of the political organization. Life
already shows in which direction the change will be made. Not in
increasing the powers of the State, but in resorting to free organization
and free federation in all those branches which are now considered as
attributes of the State." Kropotkin, "Anarchist Communism," pp. 28-29.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-50" id="linknote-50"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
50 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-50">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ On this subject there is
an excellent discussion in the before-mentioned work of Monsieur Naquet.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-51" id="linknote-51"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
51 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-51">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "As to the third—the
chief—objection, which maintains the necessity of a government for
punishing those who break the law of society, there is so much to say
about it that it hardly can be touched incidentally. The more we study the
question, the more we are brought to the conclusion that society itself is
responsible for the anti-social deeds perpetrated in its midst, and that
no punishment, no prisons, and no hangmen can diminish the numbers of such
deeds; nothing short of a reorganization of society itself. Three-quarters
of all the acts which are brought every year before our courts have their
origin, either directly or indirectly, in the present disorganized state
of society with regard to the production and distribution of wealth—not
in the perversity of human nature. As to the relatively few anti-social
deeds which result from anti-social inclinations of separate individuals,
it is not by prisons, nor even by resorting to the hangmen, that we can
diminish their numbers. By our prisons, we merely multiply them and render
them worse. By our detectives, our `price of blood,' our executions, and
our jails, we spread in society such a terrible flow of basest passions
and habits, that he who should realize the effects of these institutions
to their full extent, would be frightened by what society is doing under
the pretext of maintaining morality. We must search for other remedies,
and the remedies have been indicated long since." Kropotkin, "Anarchist
Communism," pp. 31-32.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-52" id="linknote-52"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
52 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-52">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "Anarchist Communism," p.
27.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-53" id="linknote-53"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
53 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-53">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ This was written before
the author had any personal experience of the prison system. He personally
met with nothing but kindness at the hands of the prison officials.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-54" id="linknote-54"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
54 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-54">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Bell, 1917.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-55" id="linknote-55"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
55 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-55">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Walter Scott Publishing
Company, 1906, p. 262.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-56" id="linknote-56"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
56 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-56">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ This was written in
March, 1918, almost the darkest moment of the war.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-57" id="linknote-57"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
57 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-57">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "L'Anarchie et le
Collectivisme," p. 114.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-58" id="linknote-58"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
58 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-58">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Which we discussed in
Chapter IV.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-59" id="linknote-59"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
59 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-59">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ "Self-Government in
Industry," G. Bell & Sons, 1917, pp. 110-111.]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-60" id="linknote-60"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
60 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-60">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ Some may fear that the
result would be an undue increase of population, but such fears I believe
to be groundless. See above, (Chapter IV, on "Work and Pay." Also, Chapter
vi of "Principles of Social Reconstruction" (George Allen and Unwin,
Ltd.).]</p>
<p><br/><SPAN name="linknote-61" id="linknote-61"> </SPAN></p>
<p class="foot">
61 (<SPAN href="#linknoteref-61">return</SPAN>)<br/> [ See the discussion of
this question in the preceding chapter.]</p>
<SPAN name="endofbook"></SPAN>
<div style="break-after:column;"></div><br />